Truth and Falsity: Whether they Overlap or Possess Distinct Borders

The boundaries between truth and falsehood in the context of Plato's theory. Perception of the truth and falsity of the universe. Language and sensations in the system of cognition. Development of a theory of boundaries between truth and falsehood.

Рубрика Философия
Вид статья
Язык английский
Дата добавления 26.04.2023
Размер файла 17,5 K

Отправить свою хорошую работу в базу знаний просто. Используйте форму, расположенную ниже

Студенты, аспиранты, молодые ученые, использующие базу знаний в своей учебе и работе, будут вам очень благодарны.

Размещено на http://www.allbest.ru/

Truth and Falsity: Whether they Overlap or Possess Distinct Borders

Pavlo Sodomora

Doctor of Philosophical Sciences, Professor, Lviv National Medical University (Lviv, Ukraine)

Lyubov Gutor

PhD in Education, Associate Professor,Lviv National Medical University (Lviv, Ukraine)

The boundaries between truth and falsity are being assessed in the context of Plato s theory of recollection. The nature of knowledge is seen as quite elusive, and this is why it evokes a need for questioning the notion of truth. Most important theories of truth are analyzed and taken to consideration in order to assess the boundaries of truth andfalsity. The question of truth andfalsity is being discussed in the context of broader topic of perception of the Universe. This is why the place of language and sensations is analyzed in the frame of cognizance. Theories of modern and post-modern thinkers are seen as a continuation of some statements made by Plato. Some approaches to cognizance of the Universe are evaluated in the diachronic aspect in order to develop a suitable theory of boundaries between truth and falsity. Approaches to paradoxes related to knowledge and deception are assessed in order to specify the distinction between truth and falsity. Machine assistance in the process of decision making is analyzed.

Keywords: truth, knowledge, cognizance, reminiscence, deception

Introduction. Universe and Paradox

truth lie theory knowledge

This is the third article in the series of essays aimed at interpreting Plato's dialogues “Cratylus,” “Meno,” and “Alribiades-1” in terms of language learning (versus acquisition), the nature of knowledge (versus cognizance), and, finally, or thirdly, on the borders of truth and falsity. The first article in the series discussed primarily the problem of language acquisition in comparison to language learning. As a result, it has been defined that Plato's theory of reminiscence appeared to be significantly profound in terms of modern theories of language (Sodomora & Yerchenko, 2021) despite the fact that the theory of reminiscence itself at the first glimpse seems to be pretty vague to some extent, as well as it can be neither proved nor supported by any experiment. Furthermore, this theory, as a continuation to the aforementioned problem discussed in the article, can be extrapolated to the question on the nature of knowledge, e.g., when we know something but are not quite sure whether the known fact is true or false, since belief can be false as well, as it was shown in the second article (Sodomora & Yahelo, 2021). These statements settle the third question, which consequently is being assessed in this article, namely the question on truth and falsity, as well as on the borders between these two opposites, since they are believed to be such.

These questions have been asked since time began, insofar as the answers to who we are and where we are going are still pending. This article, being far from providing sufficient answers to these eternal questions, is aimed, taking into account Plato's theory of reminiscence, to shed some light on clarification of the boundaries between truth and falsity we deal with in our daily life. Quite possibly, there is always some paradox being relied upon, at least implicitly, as we form conclusions, which makes the latter to some extent illogical. This is why, as it was said in the two previous articles on the basis of language and knowledge, consideration of borders between truth and falsity might require discussing several paradoxes. Since the nature of knowledge appears to be quite elusive, this provides us with the need for questioning the notion of truth. Consequently, if truth's being truth is to depend on the total absence of falsity, their borders are to be taken as clearly distinct. However, this requires more precise insight into broader problems, linked to the issue.

The problem of perception of the Universe is being discussed widely by scholars (Bazaluk, 2021), but apparently there is a distinction between so-called “our Universe,” or the one we observe, and the one which is outside of us. Again, while assessing the correctness of names as images of things, Plato in the “Cratylus” (432c) asserts that an image cannot represent a thing in its full perfectness, as well as in the opposite case, as he says, there would be “two Cratyluses” instead of the only one. The assertion concludes that correctness does not presuppose identical likeness of a thing and an image. Plato continues as it follows: “Do you not perceive how far images are from possessing the same qualities as the originals which they imitate?” (Plato, Cratylus 432d). Presumably, this is what much later Immanuel Kant meant by distinguishing between noumena and phenomena, and this is why he claimed that cognizance of a thing was impossible, but this topic is to be discussed elsewhere.

This is how the third question, of truth and falsity, can be settled on the basis of the two previous discussions, which analyzed the paradoxical nature of language and knowledge. In fact, basic principles of cognizance of the Universe due to their elusiveness cannot steer clear of paradoxes. It was shown that a series of aporia developed by Zeno puzzled not only Aristotle, but all upcoming generations of thinkers and contributed significantly to the development of a variety of theories and approaches to different issues. The further development of the problem of knowledge to some extent involves so-called “twofold ignorance”, which questions what exactly can be called “knowledge,” and what does not belong to it by definition. However, despite this fact, it leads to a positive result. This question was discussed in the aforementioned articles and it seems logical to continue the topic with a discussion of truth and falsity as well as assessing their boundaries.

1. Truth and Knowledge

One fundamental problem linked to the process of learning is truth. Language, being a means of cognizance of the Universe, resembles the progress from less to more perfect, although Zeno's paradoxes reveal to us the paradoxical nature of language and point at inherent inconsistencies in the process of understanding of reality. It is highly arguable that the phenomenon of language possesses clear and explainable nature, since it seems not to be unambiguously explained by behavioristic theories (Skinner, 1992). The standard epistemological objection to it is that it possesses to some extent paradoxical nature we are unable to explain by any of methods available (Chomsky, 2002). As a result, this view adds significantly to the development and improvement of newer approaches to the process of learning in general and obtaining reliable knowledge in particular, and epistemologists have been working for a quite long time towards what they hope is going to be a non-skeptical conception of knowledge (Lehrer, 1965), but this approach is to be addressed later.

There is no proof that gives us the right to assert that we possess any reliable knowledge, and this is why aiming at investigating the notion and foundation of the concept of knowledge is directed at clarifying what exactly the knowledge consists of. First, according to Plato, it is impossible to learn anything if we lack knowledge about ourselves. In this article, an attempt has been made to assess the boundaries between truth and falsity in terms of their application to reality. Again, the reality can be seen differently, as it was shown in the previous article, and this is why the relation between truth and falsity is to be assessed more precisely.

In general, knowledge is usually identified as justified true belief, or JTB. This is what can be inferred from Plato's “Meno” as well as from other dialogues (Pritchard et al., 2018). As a rule, JTB is the departing point for scholars to start investigating the concept of knowledge, which was primarily initiated by Plato. The majority of modern theories differentiate between knowledge and belief (Unger, 1968: 157-170), and this is the riddle posed by Socrates at the end of his “Meno.” As usually, Socrates provides a somewhat enigmatic and elusive distinction between knowledge and true belief, as well as Plato never provides the explicit answer in his dialogues. It is convenient for a distinction to be generalized into a more wide- ranging concept of truth in general.

It seems that the difficulty in defining the notion cannot be confined to Plato's theory exclusively, as well as it still remains problematic (Meadows, 2013: 221-240). The elusiveness of the definition of knowledge generates challenges to the philosophical tradition. This is why the definition of knowledge of a proposition as justified true belief in some contexts is not considered as a sufficient one. The problems arise in cases of either actual or possible situations in which someone has a belief that is both true and well supported by evidence. Still, as is believed by many epistemologists, it fails to be knowledge. The extensive debate was initiated with a single two-and-a-half-page article (Gettier, 1963). Gettier's article triggered a period of pronounced and renovated epistemological debates and innovations that, to some extent, can be applied to the definition of truth.

As a rule, while talking of knowledge in general, the majority of epistemologists are referring to propositional knowledge (Ichikawa, 2018), which is knowledge of a truth or known fact, or knowledge of how the world is constructed in any respect, which is described by a given occurrence. Following the words of Plato, if we do not fully understand ourselves, we will not be able to fully understand what it is either. That is a possibility, as philosophers have long realized, and these in their own way were settled by Plato, not solved though. In case if JTB is false as it has been shown by the riddle, it is evident that it should be replaced with something newer. Unfortunately, Gettier himself made no suggestions about any replacement, which resembles Plato's style of dialogues. But philosophy always settles questions, while other sciences aim to look for answers (Deely, 2001: 238). There has been an attempt to provide answers for defining boundaries between truth and falsity by machine assistance, which is to be discussed in the last chapter of the article.

As well as it can be seen, JTB form of analysis of knowledge presupposes three individually necessary and sufficient conditions for certain knowledge. For instance, to obtain knowledge that you are a living being, three prerequisites are required, namely: 1) you have to believe in this; 2) the belief is supposed to be true; 3) it is supposed to be based on good or sufficient evidence. The biggest problem, as it can be inferred from previous articles in this series, can be encountered in the last statement, since Zeno would not consider experience-based evidence of Achilles being faster than the tortoise as a valid rejection to his aporia. Consequently, this way of thinking questions the truth of the primary proposition.

There are other weak sides of JTB analysis as well which are disclosed by Gettier's paradox. Imagine that someone, who is looking at the farm, sees something that seems to be a horse. Consequently, the only belief which instantly occurs to someone, who is looking at the farm, is that there is a horse at the farm. Coincidentally, he is right, because there is a horse in the far end of the field behind the hill, but it cannot be seen, and the only animal, which can be seen, is a bull that looks like a horse. There is no direct evidence of presence of the horse in this very field, although the statement has been made correctly, and belief is true and justified, since someone, who is looking at the farm, trusts his eyes. However, such JTB cannot be considered valid knowledge (Hetherington, 2001). With this quite simplified example, it would be interesting to consider what astronomers are able to see while looking into the telescope. Their beliefs, while being true, are supposed to be supported by something else in order to become valid knowledge.

On the other hand, experiments, which are aimed at proving similar beliefs as well as at avoiding justifications that are present within each and every case to be false, can go wrong due to infinite series of unpredictable circumstances and hindrances. As a result, it can be inferred from this that the justification indicates only the fact that the belief is true to some extent, but it does not prove conclusively that it is true absolutely. This is how justification still stays open at least the possibility that the belief is false. This is what Plato speaks about in his “Meno,” providing us with an example of Dedalus' effigies (Meno 97e). Plato questions whether such knowledge possesses the required validity to be compared to the higher type in order to be called valid knowledge.

On the other hand, such cases can contain a good portion of luck which makes it impossible to prove that they cannot be called knowledge. In fact, this is the most distinctive of Gettier cases. Consider, for example, the case with Columbus' enterprise. Despite the fact that he was ignorant of the existence of two Americas, he was to some extent knowledgeable of the spherical shape of the Earth. However, not only this: he appeared to be extremely lucky to complete his four round-trips. Consequently, despite of Columbus' ignorance, the outcome was immense and it is highly questionable whether the falsity his ignorance comprised can be equated to the falsity of flat shape of Earth or not. It can be concluded that there exists certain degree of falsity, which contributes to falsity's being either less false, or more inclined to truth. It appears that when certain abnormal or favorable circumstance is present in this or that case, this circumstance can make quite fortuitous the existence of justified and true belief despite the fact that it is not supported by strong evidence. This, in its own turn, blurs the boundaries between the two opposites, i.e., truth and falsity.

2. Truth by the Means of Language

Since we communicate mostly via the means of language, the relation between truth and meaning is to be assessed as the place where truth and language relate closely. Insofar as the theory of meaning is notoriously broad (Higginbotham, 1989: 153-174), some scholars use the theory of truth as part of the theory of meaning (Glanzberg, 2013). The first sort of theory of meaning, or semantic theory, is a theory that assigns semantic contents to expressions of a language. The second sort of theory of meaning, a foundational theory, is a theory which states the facts in virtue of which expressions have the semantic contents that they have (Speaks, 2021). Some expressions might be context-sensitive or indexical. Within a propositional semantics, we can say that certain expressions possess different contents relative to distinct contexts. However, the phenomenon of context-sensitivity is one that any semantic theory recognizes. This is why many philosophers and linguists think that one or more of these categories of expressions are indexicals (Johnston, 1988: 28-42). As it can be observed, virtually every natural language expression is context-sensitive, which gives a good soil for deception.

This is why any theory of truth conditions can be applied to the theory of meaning. This category of research is pretty broad and there are different approaches to it. It would be expedient to look at what Plato says in this context in “Cratylus” (436 b): “Do you not see that he who in his inquiry after things follows names and examines into the meaning of each one runs great risks of being deceived?” More than twenty centuries later, L. Wittgenstein expressed the idea that humans do not communicate via words, but via images (Sutton, 2015: 409-443). This view was widely accepted and lively discussed in broad academic circles and contributed significantly to the development of science. Not actually being a follower of Plato, Wittgenstein initiated the process of studying language through the perspective of other disciplines (Kripke, 1982), and this subject was discussed earlier (Sodomora & Yerchenko, 2021). However, images can be distorted due to differences in perception, and this poses a significant thread to their truthfulness or correctness, as it is said in the aforementioned quotation of Plato's “Cratylus.” Again, Bertrand Russel claimed that false propositions pose a problem, but he was far from the first one who pointed at this controversy. Consequently, there has been an extensive debate among epistemologists on the definition of truth (Glanzberg, 2021).

One of the most significant approaches to the definition of truth is so-called correspondence theory which is concerned with the relation between propositions and the world. It presupposes that a proposition is true when the world contains a fact that is structurally similar to the proposition (David, 2018). Again, this has not been noticed for the first time, since Aristotle had spoken about it a quite long time ago in his “Metaphysics” (r 7.27): “to say of what is that it is, or of what is not that it is not, is true” (Aristotle, 2009). The basic idea of correspondence was captured in this quotation, as some scholars suggest (Tarski, 1944: 341-375). This Aristotle's saying was refined and clarified more extensively later, and correspondence relation is explicated as a representation relation, since a truth bearer is called true if it represents a fact (Ross, 1928). However, this theory only exacerbated further discussions on the subject, since there is an ambiguity on what can be called a fact. Reliance of truth on belief is a key point of Joachim's theory, which claims that any belief is true if and only if it is part of a coherent system of beliefs (Joachim, 1906).

However, any system which seems to be coherent today, can be questioned some time later. More pragmatical point is expressed by Peirce, as well as he is usually understood as holding the view that truth is the end of inquiry, or truth is something which is satisfactory to believe (Glanzberg, 2021).

As it can be inferred, it is not entirely clear what scholars mean by suggested definitions, partially due to the complicacy of the subject as well as due to its elusiveness. Probably due to this elusiveness Tarski's definition of “semantic conception of truth” (Tarski, 1944) lacks precise explanation, following to a certain degree Plato's approach. It is not entirely clear what exactly Tarski had in mind by defining this conception, but it can be assumed that Tarski's theory defines truth for sentences in terms of concepts like reference and satisfaction. They are intimately related to the basic semantic functions of names and predicates. Primarily, Tarski was concerned with so-called “liar paradox” (Beall & Glansberg 2020) that it would make theories in languages containing a truth predicate inconsistent (Ray, 2018: 695-717). This was especially important to his own correspondence theory, but whether it provides any substantial philosophical account of truth at all or not, is still a matter of controversy.

The liar paradox, which is also called “Epimenides paradox,” since Epimenides from Crete, according to tradition, is known for saying that all Cretans are liars, has created an enormous number of debates, discussions and articles since it was introduced. Some scholars argue that this paradox shows, among other issues, essential “incompleteness” of the world (Grim, 1991), at least to some, though uncertain, degree. Some assert that the paradox shows the importance of context in language (Glanzberg, 2018), and this assertion seems to resemble Aristotle's principle of noncontradiction. Nevertheless, what is the most intriguing; it is that liar paradox shows that the notion of truth is a vague notion (McGee, 1991). This can be taken as evidence (of which has been said earlier) that truth is far from being a fully objective matter. It is not independent of us, of our thoughts, or of context. It can be argued instead, that truth is rather constrained by our abilities to verify it. This is why it is constrained by our epistemic stance since it is to some degree an epistemic matter, and far from being an objective matter. This is why Tarski in previously cited work, expressed the opinion that the ordinary notion of truth is incoherent and far from being scientific.

Consequently, if images we communicate via can become distorted, if words do not represent the essence of things, if the truth is difficult to determine, it seems that falsity cannot be fleshed out in order to avoid being trapped by it. This is what so-called redundancy theory is concerned with. It holds that there is no property of truth at all, and appearances of the expression “true” in our sentences are redundant, which means they have no effect on what we express (Forbes, 1986: 27-54). This is why the truth, exactly as knowledge, is difficult to identify.

Conclusions: Boundaries Between Opposites

Since it is highly questionable if a proposition can be absolutely true, the question arises to what extent some propositions are true or false, as it has been shown in Columbus' example. This is why there has been a variety of attempts to solve the difficulties posed by the aforementioned series of paradoxes. One of them is so-called “infallibilist” approach, which claims that only fallible support can be provided for any belief. However, this is what Descartes wrote about in his “Meditations,” i.e., overreliance on external senses, which can fail to provide us with reliable knowledge. This is why we rarely obtain infallible justificatory support for any belief, and this is why we are not infallible knowers of truth, and we are fallible instead, which means that we are not knowers at all. However, this reaction to paradoxes is regarded as not appropriate one since epistemologists strive to understand how we obtain at least some knowledge.

Plato never provides clear answers to questions he settles, and he gives only cues “that guide rightly,” as Socrates says in “Meno” (99a), on what exactly true opinion and knowledge this case can be. As a result, ignorance (either simple or twofold) is a cause for mistakes, and wrong opinions or beliefs which turn to be a “twofold ignorance” cause false beliefs, as Socrates says in “Alcibiades” (118a), as it was discussed earlier (Sodomora & Yahelo, 2021). Still, the puzzle remains that, in spite of the fact that we might opine that each of us produces sentences which express true propositions, we clearly disagree with each other (Lasersohn, 2005: 643-686). What can be suggested here as an answer is a resemblance of St. Thomas' “negative theology,” which claims that the only knowledge that can be obtained about God is “what he is not” (Deely, 2001: 290-297). It seems that these words can be applied to knowledge in general, although this view can be seen as rather skeptical.

Therefore, since the total absence of falsity is required for belief's being knowledge, most beliefs can cease to be knowledge at all. On the other hand, so-called “negative” approach places us well too far from obtaining any sufficient answers. This is where some epistemologists suggest applying “no false evidence proposal” in order to develop a non- skeptical approach, as it has already been mentioned in another context (Lehrer, 1965: 16875). According to the suggestion, the only thing which is required for belief to be knowledge is the absence of significant element of falsity only. It means that wrong beliefs that are being used as evidence in obtaining reliable knowledge are eliminable. This is why this kind of justification is adequate for belief's being knowledge. Therefore, since false evidence sometimes plays a significant role in knowledge, such belief is far from being knowledge. This approach appears to be quite weak as well, since false evidence is to be eliminated to some unknown extent. Therefore, this still has yet to make significant inroads among scholars, and answers from epistemologists are still being awaited.

There were other approaches to the problem of identification of falsity and eliminating false evidences. Since the beginning of the Industrial Era, humanity's overreliance on machines and computers has become expressively owerwhelming. This is why there has been wide range of attempts to involve computers into the process of distinguishing of truth from falsity. However, they proved to be of little help, since, for example, lie-detection techniques developed in the 20th century are notoriously inaccurate. Partially it is so because there is a need to look for some answers behind the science. Scholars and scientists became excessively obsessed with computers and calculations, but identifying falsities appears to be more elusive and subtle to be performed by artificial intelligence, which is still far from being perfect. Neither computer, nor any other machine can identify elusive and blurred boundaries between truth and falsity.

According to statistics, commonly applied academic standards of scientific evidence are usually misleading and fail to meet necessary standards to be at least slightly above chance (McKelvey, 2021). It has been shown that humans are no better than chance at detecting deception (Mann et al., 2004: 137-149). And, as well as Plato's theory of reminiscence can be proved neither by experience, nor by five basic senses, the boundaries between truth and falsity are elusive and cannot be distinctly set by any scientific method available today. It is difficult to do this, since being humans, we are highly biased.

References

Aristotle (2009) Metaphysics. Available online: http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/metaphysics. html

Bazaluk, Oleg (2021) The Idea of “Philosophy-as-a-way-of-Life” in Plato's Dialogs. Filosofiya-Philosophy, Volume 30, Number 3, 223-230. https://doi.org/10.53656/ phil2021-03-01

Beall, Jc, and Michael Glansberg (2020) Liar Paradox. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/liarparadox/#ParaBroaPhen

Chomsky, Noam (2002) On Nature and Language. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

David, Marian (2018) The correspondence theory of truth. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/truth-correspondence/

Deely, John (2001) Four Ages of Understanding. Toronto, University of Toronto Press.

Forbes, Graeme (1986) Truth, Correspondence and Redundancy. In G. Macdonald and C. Wright, eds., Fact, Science and Morality: Essays on A.J. Ayer's “Language, Truth & Logic.” Oxford, Basil Blackwell.

Gettier, Edmund (1963) Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Analysis, 23 (6), 121-123. https://doi.org/10.2307/3326922

Glanzberg, Michael (2021) Truth. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/truth/

Glanzberg, Michael (2018) The Oxford Handbook of Truth. Oxford University Press.

Grim, Patrick (1991) The Incomplete Universe. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Hetherington, Stephen (2001) Good Knowledge, Bad Knowledge: On Two Dogmas of Epistemology. Oxford University Press.

Higginbotham, James (1989) Knowledge of reference, in Reflections on Chomsky. A. George (ed.), Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Ichikawa, Jonathan (2018) The Analysis of Knowledge. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/ knowledge-analysis/

Joachim, Harold (1906) The Nature of Truth. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Johnston, Mark (1988) The End of the Theory of Meaning. Mind & Language, 3(1), 28-42. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0017.1988.tb00131.x

Kripke, Saul (1982) Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language: An Elementary Exposition. Harvard University Press.

Lasersohn, Peter (2005) Context Dependence, Disagreement, and Predicates of Personal Taste. Linguistics and Philosophy, 28(6), 643-686. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988- 005-0596-x

Lehrer, Keith (1965) Knowledge, Truth and Evidence. Analysis, 25, 168-175. https://doi. org/10.1093/analys/25.5.168

Mann, Samanta, Vrij, Aldert, and Bull, Ray (2004) Detecting True Lies: Police Officers' Ability to Detect Suspects' Lies. Journal of Applied Psychology, 89 (1), 137-149. https://doi.org/10.1037/0021-9010.89.L137

McGee, Vann (1991) Truth, Vagueness, and Paradox. Indianapolis: Hackett.

McKelvey, Tara (2021) Military officers condemn CIA torture as a stain on America. Available online: https://www.bbc.com/news/world-us-canada-59124419

Meadows, Toby (2013) Truth, dependence and supervaluation: Living with the ghost. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42(2), 221-240. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-011-9219-x

Plato (1921) Works in 12 vol. Vol. 12. (H. Fowler, Trans.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press; London: William

Heinemann Ltd. Available online:http://www.perseus.tufts. edu/hopper/text?doc=plat.+crat.+383a.

Pritchard, Dunkan, Turn, John, and Carter, Adam (2018) The Value of Knowledge. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/ cgi-bin/encyclopedia/archinfo.cgi?entry=knowledge-value

Ray, Greg (2018) Tarski on the concept of truth. The Oxford Handbook of Truth. M. Glanzberg (ed.).

Skinner, Burrhus (1992) Verbal Behavior. Copley Publishing Group.

Sodomora, Pavlo, and Oleh Yerchenko (2021) Paradoxical Nature of Language in Terms of its Acquisition and Learning (Based on Plato's Cratylus). Philosophy and Cosmology, Volume 26, 123-131. https://doi.org/10.29202/phil-cosm/26/10

Sodomora, Pavlo, and Svitlana Yahelo (2021) The Assessment of Knowledge, or Whether We Possess Knowledge or Twofold Ignorance about Our Place in the Universe. Philosophy and Cosmology, Volume 27, 206-222. https://doi.org/10.29202/phil- cosm/27/17

Speaks, Jeff (2021) Theories of Meaning. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/cgi-bin/encyclopedia/archinfo.cgi?entry=meaning.

Sutton, John (2015) Remembering as Public Practice: Wittgenstein, Memory, and Distributed Cognitive Ecologies. Mind, Language and Action. https://doi. org/10.1515/9783110378795.409

Tarski, Alfred (1944) The semantic conception of truth. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 4, No. 3, 341-376.

Unger, Peter (1968) An Analysis of Factual Knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 65, No. 6, 157-170. https://doi.org/10.2307/2024203

Размещено на Allbest.ru

...

Подобные документы

  • Confucianism as the source of the fundamental outlook for the Chinese. The history of its occurrence during the reign of the Han dynasty. Significant differences of this philosophy from other major canons. Idealistic views on the development of society.

    презентация [889,1 K], добавлен 13.11.2014

  • Language picture of the world, factors of formation. The configuration of the ideas embodied in the meaning of the words of the native language. Key ideas for Russian language picture of the world are. Presentation of the unpredictability of the world.

    реферат [17,2 K], добавлен 11.10.2015

  • A proverb as a simple and concrete saying popularly known and repeated, which expresses a truth, based on common sense or the practical experience of humanity. Confucius as the most famous creator of proverbs. Grammatical structures of proverbs.

    презентация [895,6 K], добавлен 05.04.2013

  • The study of political discourse. Political discourse: representation and transformation. Syntax, translation, and truth. Modern rhetorical studies. Aspects of a communication science, historical building, the social theory and political science.

    лекция [35,9 K], добавлен 18.05.2011

  • A cosmological model to explain the origins of matter, energy, space, time the Big Bang theory asserts that the universe began at a certain point in the distant past. Pre-twentieth century ideas of Universe’s origins. Confirmation of the Big Bang theory.

    реферат [37,2 K], добавлен 25.06.2010

  • Theory of economics was created and is developed by the economists of different schools. Main article: History of Economics. Areas of study. Techniques. Language and reasoning. Development of economic thought. The system of economic relations.

    реферат [22,6 K], добавлен 12.05.2008

  • St. Patrick, the patron saint of Ireland, is one of Christianity's most widely known figures. Taken Prisoner By Irish Raiders. No Irish Need Apply. Wearing of the Green Goes Global. Other Superstitions. The Truth about Saint Patrick. Sayings and Toasts.

    реферат [21,6 K], добавлен 04.05.2009

  • The term "political system". The theory of social system. Classification of social system. Organizational and institutional subsystem. Sociology of political systems. The creators of the theory of political systems. Cultural and ideological subsystem.

    реферат [18,8 K], добавлен 29.04.2016

  • History of interpreting and establishing of the theory. Translation and interpreting. Sign-language communication between speakers. Modern Western Schools of translation theory. Models and types of interpreting. Simultaneous and machine translation.

    курсовая работа [45,2 K], добавлен 26.01.2011

  • Analysis of Rousseau's social contract theory and examples of its connection with the real world. Structure of society. Principles of having an efficient governmental system. Theory of separation of powers. The importance of censorship and religion.

    статья [13,1 K], добавлен 30.11.2014

  • Theoretical problems of linguistic form Language. Progressive development of language. Polysemy as the Source of Ambiguities in a Language. Polysemy and its Connection with the Context. Polysemy in Teaching English on Intermediate and Advanced Level.

    дипломная работа [45,3 K], добавлен 06.06.2011

  • Definition of Leadership. Trait theory. How this theory works. Origin and Analysis and basics Pre-conditions for effective use of Trait theory. Inborn leadership characteristics. Process of impact and interaction among the leader and his followers.

    реферат [436,9 K], добавлен 24.09.2014

  • Public choice is an application of neoclassical economic tools. James Buchanan the developer of the Theory of the Public choice. The most important contribution of Public Choice Theory is that it recognizes that politicians are motivated by self interest.

    презентация [273,0 K], добавлен 03.04.2012

  • Influence psychology of cognitive activity and cognitive development on student’s learning abilities during study. Cognitive development theory in psychology. Analysis of Jean Piaget's theory. Her place among the other concept of personal development.

    презентация [1,3 M], добавлен 13.04.2016

  • Globalization of the theory, ideology and practice of modern constitutionalism on the border of millennia. The development of the constitutional ideas and institutes. Analyze the model of the Ukrainian constitutionalism and its realization in practice.

    реферат [25,5 K], добавлен 07.01.2015

  • One of the long-established misconceptions about the lexicon is that it is neatly and rigidly divided into semantically related sets of words. In contrast, we claim that word meanings do not have clear boundaries.

    курсовая работа [19,7 K], добавлен 30.11.2002

  • Development of harmonious and competent personality - one of main tasks in the process of teaching of future teachers. Theoretical aspects of education and competence of teacher of foreign language are in the context of General European Structure.

    контрольная работа [12,2 K], добавлен 16.05.2009

  • The central elements of the original Community method. A new "intergovernmentalist" school of integration theory emerged, liberal intergovernmentalism. Constructivism, and reshaping European identities and preferences and integration theory today.

    практическая работа [29,4 K], добавлен 20.03.2010

  • Constitutionalism as political and legal theory and practice of development of the constitutional democratic state and civil society. Principles of modern constitutional system of board. Role of society in the course of formation of municipal authority.

    реферат [18,5 K], добавлен 07.01.2015

  • Methods of foreign language teaching and its relation to other sciences. Psychological and linguistic prerequisites for foreign language teaching. Aims, content and principles language learning. Teaching pronunciation, grammar, speaking and writing.

    курс лекций [79,6 K], добавлен 13.03.2015

Работы в архивах красиво оформлены согласно требованиям ВУЗов и содержат рисунки, диаграммы, формулы и т.д.
PPT, PPTX и PDF-файлы представлены только в архивах.
Рекомендуем скачать работу.