Nature and essential characteristics of classical rationality
Explication of the characteristics of the classical mind. Formation of archetypal principles of Western rationality. Deconstruction of the classical understanding of the substantiality of history. Clarifications of the features of the classical mind.
Ðóáðèêà | Êóëüòóðà è èñêóññòâî |
Âèä | ñòàòüÿ |
ßçûê | àíãëèéñêèé |
Äàòà äîáàâëåíèÿ | 03.06.2021 |
Ðàçìåð ôàéëà | 37,9 K |
Îòïðàâèòü ñâîþ õîðîøóþ ðàáîòó â áàçó çíàíèé ïðîñòî. Èñïîëüçóéòå ôîðìó, ðàñïîëîæåííóþ íèæå
Ñòóäåíòû, àñïèðàíòû, ìîëîäûå ó÷åíûå, èñïîëüçóþùèå áàçó çíàíèé â ñâîåé ó÷åáå è ðàáîòå, áóäóò âàì î÷åíü áëàãîäàðíû.
Ðàçìåùåíî íà http://www.allbest.ru/
Nature and essential characteristics of classical rationality
V. S. Levytskyy
Ukrainian Institute of Strategies of Global Development and Adaptation
The 20th century began under the sign of deconstruction of the classical comprehension of substantiality of history, culture and mind. It turned out that each culture has its unique worldview universals and a conclusion has been made that there is a principal difference between classical and modern cultural worlds, and in the rationalities characteristic to them. In the article, based on V. Stepins conception of scientific rationality, the essential characteristics of the classical mind, which possess heuristic potentials when comparing pre-modern and modern rationality, are explicated. In particular, the ontologism of the pre-modern mind has been distinguished and substantiated based on historical and philosophical material -- rootedness in being, only partially related to man; its hierarchy is the dependence of cognitive possibilities on the ontological level of the entities opening to the mind; and the transcendence is the fundamental incomprehensibility of the bases and “guarantors” of the mind and the world for the mind itself. Within the framework of the classical mind, archetypical principles of Western rationality were formulated as such, some of which, after the secularization of medieval culture, became the principle of organizing secular social reality, which ultimately led to the emergence of a new social reality, later called Modernism.
Keywords: mind, rationality, modernity, ontology, hierarchy, transcendence.
Ïðèðîäà è ñóùíîñòíûå õàðàêòåðèñòèêè êëàññè÷åñêîé ðàöèîíàëüíîñòè
B. Ñ. Ëåâèöêèé
Óêðàèíñêèé èíñòèòóò ñòðàòåãèé ãëîáàëüíîãî ðàçâèòèÿ è àäàïòàöèè
ÕÕ ñòîëåòèå ïðîøëî ïîä çíàêîì äåêîíñòðóêöèè êëàññè÷åñêîãî ïîíèìàíèÿ ñóáñòàíöèîíàëüíîñòè èñòîðèè, êóëüòóðû, ðàçóìà. Îêàçàëîñü, ÷òî êàæäàÿ êóëüòóðà èìååò ñâîè óíèêàëüíûå ìèðîâîççðåí÷åñêèå óíèâåðñàëèè, áûë ñäåëàí âûâîä î ïðèíöèïèàëüíîì îòëè÷èè êëàññè÷åñêîãî è ìîäåðíîãî êóëüòóðíûõ ìèðîâ, à ñîîòâåòñòâåííî è ñâîéñòâåííûõ èì ðàöèîíàëüíîñòåé. Åñëè êëàññè÷åñêàÿ ðàöèîíàëüíîñòü îïèðàëàñü íà ìèôîëîãè÷åñêèå è ðåëèãèîçíûå äîìèíàíòû, òî ðàçóì ýïîõè ìîäåðíà àáñîëþòèçèðîâàë ïðîñâåùåí÷åñêèå öåííîñòè.  ñòàòüå ïðåäïðèíèìàåòñÿ ïîïûòêà óòî÷íåíèÿ ñóùåñòâåííûõ ÷åðò êëàññè÷åñêîãî ðàçóìà è åãî îòëè÷èÿ îò ñîâðåìåííîé ðàöèîíàëüíîñòè, â ÷àñòíîñòè ðåêîíñòðóèðóþòñÿ ìåñòî è çíà÷åíèå âçãëÿäîâ íà òðàíñöåíäåíòíîå â äîìîäåðíîì ðàöèîíàëüíîì äèñêóðñå, ïîä÷åðêèâàåòñÿ çíà÷åíèå ïðîöåññîâ ñåêóëÿðèçàöèè äëÿ ôîðìèðîâàíèÿ ìîäåðíîé ðàöèîíàëüíîñòè.  ñòàòüå êîíöåïöèÿ íàó÷íîé ðàöèîíàëüíîñòè, ðàçðàáîòàííàÿ Â. Ñ. Ñòåïèíûì è ïîëó÷èâøàÿ çàñëóæåííîå ïðèçíàíèå â ôèëîñîôèè íàóêè, ðàñïðîñòðàíÿåòñÿ íà áîëåå øèðîêèé êóëüòóðíûé êîíòåêñò. Ñ òî÷êè çðåíèÿ ýòîé êîíöåïöèè ïðåäïðèíèìàåòñÿ ïîïûòêà îõàðàêòåðèçîâàòü êëàññè÷åñêèé ðàçóì íà îñíîâå îíòîëîãè÷åñêîãî, ýïèñòåìîëîãè÷åñêîãî è ñóáúåêò-îáúåêòíîãî êðèòåðèåâ. Ýêñïëèêàöèÿ ñóùíîñòíûõ õàðàêòåðèñòèê êëàññè÷åñêîãî ðàçóìà èìååò ýâðèñòè÷íûé ïîòåíöèàë ïðè ñðàâíåíèè äîìîäåðíîé è ñîâðåìåííîé ðàöèîíàëüíîñòè.  ÷àñòíîñòè âûäåëÿþòñÿ è íà îñíîâå èñòîðèêî-ôèëîñîôñêîãî ìàòåðèàëà îáîñíîâûâàþòñÿ îòëè÷èòåëüíûå ÷åðòû êëàññè÷åñêîãî (äîìîäåðíîãî) ðàçóìà: åãî îíòîëîãèçì -- óêîðåíåííîñòü â áûòèè, òîëüêî ÷àñòè÷íî ñâÿçàííîì ñ ÷åëîâåêîì; èåðàðõèçì -- çàâèñèìîñòü ïîçíàâàòåëüíûõ âîçìîæíîñòåé îò îíòîëîãè÷åñêîãî óðîâíÿ îòêðûâàþùèõñÿ ðàçóìó ñóùíîñòåé è òðàíñöåíäåíòíîñòü -- ïðèíöèïèàëüíàÿ íåïîñòèæèìîñòü îñíîâàíèé è «ãàðàíòîâ» ðàçóìà è ìèðà äëÿ ñàìîãî ðàçóìà.  ðàìêàõ êëàññè÷åñêîãî ðàçóìà áûëè ñôîðìóëèðîâàíû àðõåòèïè÷åñêèå ïðèíöèïû çàïàäíîé ðàöèîíàëüíîñòè êàê òàêîâîé, ÷àñòü êîòîðûõ ïîñëå ñåêóëÿðèçàöèè ñðåäíåâåêîâîé êóëüòóðû ñòàëà ïðèíöèïîì îðãàíèçàöèè ñâåòñêîé ñîöèàëüíîé äåéñòâèòåëüíîñòè, ÷òî â êîíå÷íîì èòîãå ïîâëåêëî çà ñîáîé ôîðìèðîâàíèå íîâîé ñîöèàëüíîé ðåàëüíîñòè -- Ìîäåðíà.
Êëþ÷åâûå ñëîâà: ðàçóì, ðàöèîíàëüíîñòü, ìîäåðí, îíòîëîãèÿ, èåðàðõèÿ, òðàíñöåíäåíòíîñòü.
Every person is surely confident in his ability to use his/her own mind. Rationality for some time has generally become synonymous with civilization. At about the same time (the second half of the nineteenth century), doubts about the cultural invariance of rationality also began to creep in. Practical use of mind has become dependent on a particular cultural tradition. Inclusion in this tradition makes us confident in the adequate operation of the mind: rationality becomes a part of the norm. In this case, in an ordinary situation, the question of the basis of one's own, and especially cultural mind never arises.
The situation changes when “anomalies” appear in the discourse (using Kuhn's terminology), in the form of representatives of other cultures, or the heritage of other eras. In such situations comes an awareness of the particularity of mind of one's own culture -- even if a person believes infallibly in the superiority of his own rationality, he cannot but feel the otherness of his opponent's rationality leading to the specified stress.
It should be noted that the twentieth century began and went under the sign of the deconstruction of Hegel's (originally Christian) understanding of the substantiality of history, culture, and mind. Neo-Kantians of the Marburg school showed that the transcendental subject is culturally determined, Wittgenstein linked rationality with depth grammar, Heidegger combined linguistic and ontological imperatives, Foucault put meaning in
discourse. In the second half of the last century, and especially after the linguistic turn, the particularity of individual cultural worlds became philosophy's commonplace. It turned out that each culture has its own unique worldview universals, if we use the terminology of Stepin. Thus, this philosophical tradition comes to the necessary conclusion regarding the fundamental difference between the classical and modern cultural worlds, and their rationalities accordingly.
At the same time, many authors (Losev, Averintsev, Borodai, Sidash, Heidegger, Maritain, Gilson, Swiezawski) made the specifics of the classical period the subject of their research. They were able to identify its characteristic features and indicate some of its universal features. Against the background of these explications regarding the classical mind, a different architectonics of its modern heir is well seen.
The subject of this article is formed at the intersection of these two methodologies. On the one hand, aimed at clarifying the unique for the premodern mind and at the same time its unique foundations, on the other hand -- establishing their connection with those of its structures (principles) that the Modern Mind inherited. classical reason archetypal rationality
Before moving on to the main subject of this research, it is vital to have a clear understanding of the main terminology. We are talking about such definitions as “mind”, “intelligence”, “reason”. On the one hand, it seems that there is no problem here, and the use of these terms is quite self-evident -- we use them on a daily basis and, without the slightest difficulty, move from one to the other, often using them as synonymous. On the other hand, if we talk about the scientific problem of demarcating the meanings of these terms, then it is very difficult to reach a certain level of generalizations (for example, cultural), because even within the same cultural integrity, different authors can use these terms vari- ably1. Therefore, the following reflection is not an attempt to linguistic, but rather to semantic classification.
The thing the ancient Greeks called Siavoia (dianoia), and with which they associated discursive thinking, reasoning that is passing from one sensual subject to another, in Latin, became the ratio, and the most adequate analogue of it in Russian can be considered as reason A good example in this case is the work of Thomas Aquinas and Duns Scotus. Speaking of higher cognitive ability, which the Greeks called vouq (mind), Thomas uses the term “intellectus”, which is trans-lated into Russian with the term “mind” (sometimes intellect). In the same case, Duns Scotus along with “intellectus” and “ratio” uses the definition of “mentis”, which is generally characteristic of the Augustinian tradition of the Franciscans (“mens” is the term of St. Augustine to mean “reason”). See, respectively [1; 2]. Plato, at the end of the sixth book of the dialogue “The Republic”, gave an excellent hermeneutics of the separation of mind and reason. See “State” 511 de.. In the Russian-speaking tradition, the more well-established translation of the Latin “ratio” is “mind”, but if you follow the meaning, the more appropriate translation is still to recognize the “reason”, especially when it comes to medieval philosophy. Moreover, such a reading is quite admitted by Latin dictionaries See, for example, the interpretation of this term in the Large Latin-Russian Dictionary..
Greek vouq (nous), corresponds to the Latin intellectus and the Russian “mind”, less often the “intellect” is usedthe Soul” of Aristotle, indicates that “the translator instead of the Greek” mind “puts the Russian” mind “ which is corresponding, rather not Greek nous, but Greek dianoia [4, p. 78]. Although in the volume “Sophists. Socrates. Plato”, in the part of Plato's thinking on thinking that is devoted to analysis, uses“ mind ”and“ reason ”as interchangeable concepts [5, p. 451]. However, this remark of the Russian-Soviet scholar is intended, rather, to emphasize the difference between the understanding of the “mind” in antiquity (which is sometimes translated as intelligence) and the “mind” of modern philosophy. (due to the greater everydayness of the meaning of the latter).
In philosophical literature, it is customary to use “reason” However, despite the fact that “reason” is a more commonly used term in philosophical literature, the Russian language still captured the essential characteristic of this type of knowledge in the word speculation (óìîçðåíèå), which indicates intelligent vision (óìíîå çðåíèå), when by analogy with the eye, the mind seizes the intelligible image as a whole. rather than “mind” if it is not a question of special studies dedicated to, for example, the philosophy of Aristotle, Plotinus or Proclus. This is the highest intellectual ability of a person, the main characteristic of which is associated with the intuitive grasp of truth as a whole -- this is not thinking, but knowledge, vision, contemplation Analyzing Plotinus's legacy, Averintsev summarized the difference between reason and mind (intel-ligence) very succinctly: “The founder of Neo-Platonism, Plotinus contrasts the alphabet with the Egyptian hieroglyph: the sign system of the alphabet, like the discursive work of reason, parses the word into“ ele-ments ”and then mechanically assembles it from them, but more noble is the symbolism of the hieroglyph offering our “vision,” the intuition of our mind is a holistic and indecomposable eidos» [7, p. 87].. This position typical of ancient philosophy was well understood by the Church Fathers, so Anthony the Great wrote: “The body's organ of vision is the eye, the soul's organ of view is the mind... The soul that lacks a good mind and a good life is blind. The eye sees the visible, and the mind perceives the invisible. The God- loving mind is the light of the soul. Those who have a God-loving mind are enlightened by the heart and see God with the mind Archpriest Leonov gives a good difference analysis for the difference between “mind”, “intelligence” and “reason” in patristic literature, showing that the price for sin was the “slide” from the contemplative mind to the reasoning mind [6].” (cit. by: [6]).
It should be said that even though the use of the category “mind” in modern philosophical discourse will be perceived rather as a kind of rudiment, the archetype of the dichotomous division of cognitive ability remains unchanged throughout the history of the development of Western philosophy. Even Kant, with the revolution he had accomplished, could not do anything with the structure of the Greek-scholastic heritage. The only thing he managed to do was to add new content to these categories, although this Copernican revolution, which is crucial for the West, can be organically written into the history of the development of European nominalism, showing that this revolution is only a radicaliza- tion of the existing tradition.
Having some terminological subtleties clarified, we can go directly to the foundations of the classical mind, which constitute its being. Despite the fact that the subject of further consideration will be the pre-modern classical mind, scientific research must take into account the transformations of the rationality that has occurred and resulted in the birth of scientific rationality itself. Speaking of various types of scientific rationality that underlie classical, non-classical and post-non-classical science, Stepin, on the basis of the structure of the foundations of science proposed by him, identifies three criteria that determine them: 1) the peculiarity of the systemic organization of objects that make up the subject of scientific research, 2) instrumental and methodological features of cognitive activity, 3) features of subject-object relations between the scientist and the subject of science. The first criterion, by its nature, is ontological and reflects the scientific community's ideas about the world under study, the second, epistemological, fixes the most adequate ways of the researcher's cognitive interaction with reality, the third characterizes the scientific community's ideas about the goals and possibilities of the scientific mind as such. Taking into account the deserved authority of ViacheslavStepin's concept received in the philosophy of science, it seems justified to extend it to a wider cultural context and try to characterize the classical mind on the basis of ontological, epistemological and subject- object criteria.
From the point of view of the “ontological” criterion, the most stable feature of the world that opened up to the classical mind as an object of its comprehension, distinguishing it from later views (for example, the mechanistic picture of the world of classical science) is its religious and mythological coloring. The world did not appear in front of a man in the form of a “picture”, but absorbed him as a necessary element of the Cosmos or Creation. The mind itself was not considered as an attribute of “humanity”, but was a structural element of the existing. From the point of view of the “epistemological” criterion, the classical mind, in accordance with the ontological hierarchy of the being, should be characterized as principally hierarchical. If we talk about the third criterion of rationality when characterizing the type of subject-object relations, then the classical mind, in accordance with the features of the basic for ancient antiquity Platonic ontology and, moreover, Christian ontology, is distinguished by the fundamental transcendence of its foundations.
In this case, classical mind is characterized by ontologism -- rootedness in being, only partially connected with a person; hierarchism -- the dependence of cognitive possibilities on the ontological level of entities that are being opened to the mind and transcendence -- the fundamental incomprehensibility of the foundations of mind and the world for the mind itself.
Ontologism of the classical mind
The mind (intelligence) for classical discourse is always a part of ontology, an essential entity in the hierarchy of the degrees of being. Hence, human cognitive activity is not a function of thinking (brain), but an existential cosmic (theological) process: knowledge (as, indeed, the sphere of practical reason), is determined ontologically, not by anthropology in the broad sense, as it is in the case of the modern mind. The idea of unity of thinking and being, starting from at least the philosophy of the Eleatics, runs like a red thread through all antiquity: you can (and need to) know only what dwells forever and never changes -- everything sensual is just an illusion that needs to be avoided. “One and the same is a thought and that to which the thought strives”, said Parmenides, “since one cannot find thoughts without being, in which this thought is realized. After all, there is and there will be nothing else other than being, since fate has tied being with completeness in itself and stillness” [8]. Thinking is a true being -- Mind is not a means (tool) of knowledge, but being itself, which thinks of itself. As Losev believed, Plato was the first who gave thinking, substantiality -- Mind, in his philosophy, became a separate substance.
The ontological nature of the foundations of reason in the works of Plato is not difficult to find. Here it can be said, firstly, that the structure of man completely repeats the structure of the cosmos: there is a body in which the soul dwells, and the mind is placed in it. This is the old idea of the coincidence of the microcosm with the macrocosm. Losev, analyzing Plato's “Timaeus”, writes: “The body, mind and soul are equal components of both God and man (30b, 70a ff.). We find a striking correspondence between the structure of the cosmos' soul (35a cl.) and the properties of the human soul (43 and 37a)... The human mind of Plato functions in the same way as the mind of the cosmos (43de-44a and 41d)” [5, p. 621]. Secondly, we can describe a more significant point, which allows us to speak about Plato's ontologism. The Demiurge himself, the creator of the world, is Mind. In Timaeus, Plato writes: “Everything said so far, with a few exceptions, pointed to phenomena created by the power of reason” It should be said that there are more emblematic translations of this passage, for example, Boroday in the monograph “The Birth of a Philosophical Concept. God and matter in the dialogues of Plato “translates it as follows”: Everything we have said so far, with minor exceptions, described things as they were created by the Demiurge's mind” [10, p. 52]. (48a) [9, p. 419], and the Russian explorer of the creativity of the Greek thinker on this basis asserts: “The text cited suggests that Plato identified the demiurge with the mind...” [10, p. 52-53]. The author of the classical translations (which in some way became canonical) of Plato's texts into Russian VasiliyKarpov wrote in this context: “Plato understood God as the highest and absolute mind, free and independent of anything outside, -- from which everything that exists, got its start” [9, p. 354-355]. The demiurge creates the world by looking at ideas See, for example, Timaeus 30b-31b, 39e. -- eternal patterns This moment fundamentally distinguishes the creationist theories of Plato and the Bible -- unlike the Plato texts, in Christianity God creates the world from nothing. It is appropriate to recall the concept of Martin Heidegger, who understood the truth of the times of antiquity as dArGsia (aletheia) and opposed it to modernity of authenticity, and considered the entire history oftheWest as oblivion of existence. See more: [12; 13]. that set the archetype and the human knowledge of truth. Avoiding the changeable, the human mind should focus on finding the eternal identities of true eidos. Thus, true knowledge for Plato lies in the contemplation of the world of ideas, genuine being, the human mind imitates the universal mind, which observes the eidos within itself. “The whole point is,” Losev writes, “that thinking, according to Plato, is primarily ontological...” [5, p. 457]. In this way, a balance of being and thinking is established and, perhaps, for the first time, the concept of self-thinking thought is developed. Climbing up the steps of thinking, one gradually gets closer to the true being, respectively, the truth is not a search for authenticity, but a contemplation (reunion) of being itself11.
From the ingenious intuitions of Plato, Aristotle developed an explicit teaching about the cosmic Mind Losev, for example, justifies a position opposite to a long tradition that comes at least from the Middle Ages, he insists that Aristotle did not criticize and deny Plato's teachings, but developed and per-fected -- it is completely wrong to understand Aristotle as an antagonist of Plato -- he is the successor of his work. Thus, in the context of the theory of the Mind, Losev writes: “In Plato's work the Mind consists of ideas, and in Aristotle's work the Mind consists of ideas in exactly the same way; and both of these Minds, both philosophers have as the same eternal and actual cosmic or rather supra-cosmic Mind” [4, p. 43].. This is the topic, to which he dedicated the XII book of his “Metaphysics”. In it, Stagirite develops the concept of God-Mind, perhaps, for many centuries ahead, defining reflection strategies on this topic. This divine Mind is motionless, unchanging, eternally relevant, having itself as a goal, thinking itself. “Thus,” Aristotle writes about this Mind, “it is clear that the mind thinks the most divine and the most worthy and is not a subject to change, because its change would be for the worse, and this is already some movement. So, firstly, if the mind is not an activity of thinking, but an ability for it, then naturally the continuity of thinking would be difficult for it. Secondly, it is clear that something else would exist, more worthy than the mind, namely, comprehended by thought ... Therefore, the mind thinks of itself if it is superior and its thinking is thinking about thinking” [11, p. 371]. Here it is important to note a few things. Firstly, the mind is a part of the structure of being, even more so, the very being. Secondly, a distinction is made between potential and actual reason, which from this time will steadily go down in the history of this question, and will be especially important for medieval philosophy. Thirdly, self-reflection (knowledge of oneself knowing and at the same time awareness of the coincidence between subject and object, if we are using the language of German classical philosophy) is substantiated as the highest form of activity.
By virtue of the existential dependence of man on this Mind and actions in his likeness, the private subjective mind can reason only because there is this eternally actual Mind. This was amply summarized by Losev, pointing to the ontological understanding of thinking in antiquity: “The potential mind, from its (Aristotle's. -- VI L.) point of view, can exist only when there is an actual energy mind. The material immersion of the mind has for itself the condition of its ability to have an immaterial mind. The passive mind, burdened with sensual representations, is possible only when there is an actual mind without any material sensuality. And, finally, the individual and subjective mind of a person has as a condition of its possibility for the existence of the universal and objective Mind” [4, p. 44-45].
The most complete form of this concept of the divine Mind was acquired in Plotinus' philosophy (if you agree with the opinion that Proclus simply developed the Plotinus' doctrine, without adding anything substantially new to it), which in this context is closer, oddly enough, to Aristotle than to Plato See the position of Losev on this subject, which then became widely replicated in many studies on the Plotinus' philosophy [15].. The founder of Neo-Platonism develops and substantiates with the new power the classical ancient idea of the unity of being and thinking (“Parmenides -- before Plato -- taught the same thing, because he connected the essence and the Mind in the identity, believing that things are not sensible things, saying that “to think and to be is the same” [14, p. 22]), and develops the Platonic-Aristotelian conception of the self-thinking thought as the essence of Mind The same idea is concisely formulated by Proclus, the finisher of the neo-Platonic tradition, in his treatise “The Fundamentals of Theology”: “167. Every mind thinks of itself, but the first mind is only of itself; and in it the mind and the intelligible are one in number” [16].: Thus, the Mind and the intelligible are one thing, it is the Being, and the first Being, it is the first Mind that has things truly or, rather, is identical with them Enneads contain dozens of arguments on this topic in this context. See, for example, En V.3.5; 4.2.” [14, p. 70].
Plotinus not only reduces everything to one reason, insisting that “all things exist thanks to the One” (En VI. 9.1), but he develops a complete cosmology that implies a strict hierarchy, supported by the emanation of the One. The Cosmic Mind turns out to be the ultimate essence about which the cataphatic discourse is possible, which, in turn, makes possible any thinking of private minds. In the Fifth Ennead, Plotinus writes: “And all things, attaining perfection, give birth; The One always gives birth perfectly and forever; while the creatures are smaller than himself. What then should be said about the absolut perfect? Nothing can happen from Him, except the following after Him in greatness. The mind is this next in greatness, and second; because the Mind sees the One and needs only Him; The One does not need Mind; born of the Superior, there can only be Mind -- Mind that surpasses all things, because other things come after Mind, for example, the Soul, which is the Logos of Mind and one of His energies, since Mind is the Mind of the One” [14, p. 18]. For antiquity, to be rational and to exist generally means to be part of the hierarchy of beings. The mind is a part of being, being itself, and therefore thinking (rational action) is not a function of the body, but an approach of the soul to the true being itself.
During the period of the Middle Ages, not only was this maxim not abandoned, but developed even more on new cultural soil. Here you can recall the work and saint Augustine, and the treatises of Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, and the heritage of St. Thomas Aquinas and others. Medieval thought absorbed many ancient developments: from the categorical apparatus and methodology to the Neo-Platonic trinity and the doctrine of entelechy. The concept of God as the supreme Mind (the second hypostasis is completely analogous to the ancient tradition), already formulated in the first lines of the Gospel of John: “In the beginning was the Word, and the Word was with God, and the Word was God” (John 1: 1) which, on the one hand, canonizes the idea of God-Mind, on the other, introduces a specifically Christian understanding of this Being -- from the faceless abstract world principle of antiquity, it turns into the personified personality of God the Son.
In the philosophical language of high scholasticism, it began to sound as follows: “Thus, we know the mind, which refers to the universal being as an act of all being, and this is the divine mind, which is the essence of God and in which everything that exists from the very beginning and virtually is preexisting as in its reason” [17, p. 92]. This excerpt from the “Summa Theologica” by Thomas Aquinas says that there is a (single) ever-pressing mind in which there are no unrealized potencies, otherwise it would not be all-knowing and not perfect, not only does the essence coincides with the existence in it, or rather even the existence and its essence, it is also a pure act, which is the cause of all things (ST I. 79. 2). In the universal hierarchy it is followed by the angelic mind, which “is always relevant in relation to the things that it thinks of because of its proximity to the first mind” (ST I. 79. 2). And finally, the last, the lowest and most distant from the perfection position is the human mind, which is potential in relation to everything intelligible.
Naturally, this entire hierarchy exists and is supported by only one reason: everything that exists is existing because of its connection with the universally existing, it draws its being and finds its main goal. Whatever happens in the world, according to the Medieval Reason, occurs solely by involvement and the higher it is, the more perfect the action is. Neretina very accurately noticed this feature of medieval culture, indicating at the same time a certain tragedy of the age: “True uncreated existence (God) was one thing, and the created thing did not merge with Him, but received communion with Him -- this eternal not-before-connectedness gave the era a special tragedy, which is conventionally called the Middle Ages” [18]. This, by the way, is one of the essential differences between the Middle Ages and antiquity: the antiquity is looking for mergers, the Middle Ages -- the sacrament. Last but not least, this is why the teachings of Averroes regarding a single intellect, followed by Siger of Brabant, Boetius of Dacia and others, were rejected. The Arabic thinker, relying on the legacy of Aristotle, primarily on the treatise “On the Soul”, argued that there is a single world mind (intellect), and individual human intellects are world particles. After death, they merge with this single intellect and cease to exist as independent substances, which naturally went against the Christian teaching about personal (individual) immortality of the soul and salvation. Actually, therefore, the best representatives of scholasticism, including Thomas Aquinas, who dedicated a special treatise to refute mono-intellectualism, opposed the teachings of Averroes.
So, the medieval mind knows the universe, in which (beyond) the God-Logos (Trinity) is at the top of the hierarchy, causing not only rational activity, but also the very being of all beings. Not only action, but also being is possible in this world solely by participation: the hierarchy of entities is determined by the hierarchy of existence. Analyzing the philosophy of Thomas Aquinas, Etienne Gilson, one of the best experts on the philosophy of Aquinas, gave a very good hermeneutics of this maxim: “Every entity, not being an act of existence, exists because of it and consists in it as its self-determination. Outside of the pure Act of being, nothing can exist in any other way than as this or that concrete existence. Consequently, it is the hierarchy of acts of existence that substantiates and regulates the hierarchy of entities, each of which expresses only the intensity of a certain act of existence” [19]. The nature and cause of the human mind (man as such) indicates pure being, transcendent to all created things: the earthly mind is the result of the existence of the Divine mind. The nature of the classical mind is deeply ontological -- rationality does not appear as the adequacy of the conventionally established norms (which is characteristic for the modern mind), or rather, this is not the ultimate level of legitimation, but these norms themselves have a transcendental rationale.
Thus, it can be stated: first, the ontologism of the foundations of the pre-modern mind; secondly, the basis of the classical mind is the Divine Mind -- the highest level of the hierarchy of beings (being itself); thirdly, thinking is an “attribute” of being, and not a function of the subject.
Hierarchism (Subordinationism) of the classical mind
The hierarchism of the pre-modern mind is well known and has been repeatedly analyzed in philosophical and theological literature. As a proof, one can simply turn to the works of Plotinus, Pseudo-Dionysius or John of the Ladder. The hierarchical structure can be easily found in the internal processes of thinking, for example, from sensory seizure through a rational movement to intelligent contemplation, in which the latter is incomparably higher in the general hierarchy. In Plato's “Republic” Socrates, after a long discussion, summarizes it as follows: “.. .at the highest level is mind, on the second -- sanity, third place one must give to faith, and the last is likeness, arrange them accordingly, considering that the more this state is participial to the truth and the more reliability it has” [20, p. 249]. You can see it in the structure of being itself, which is a system with a clear subordination, built depending on the intensity (proximity) of higher being. “And the aesthetic consciousness and its subject,” Losev writes, “are hierarchical, ranging from eternal, immovable and self-identical entities, which are principles and ideas, and ending with the physical, bodily world. Higher here is a pattern for the lower and a condition of possibility for the lower [5, p. 276]. And Gilson, when analyzing the philosophy of Thomas Aquinas, and the medieval worldview in general, wrote that the thinkers of this period were clearly aware of the dependence of any essence on the act of existence, which is the cause of its (essence) existence. Accordingly, the hierarchy of entities is a derivative of the hierarchy of existence that is showing the degree of closeness to the pure act of existence, which of course was God in medieval discourse. All this does not cause any doubt and, to a large extent, this is what distinguishes the classical mind from the modern one. The modern mind is not aware of the hierarchy of entities, and every other hierarchy that it perceives has completely different foundations.
However, the transformation process that led to the emergence of a new form of mind and culture did not occur simultaneously, and all of its prerequisites are not only in the modern discourse. Another representative of French neo-Thomism, a deep connoisseur of Aquinas philosophy, Jacques Maritain in his work “Saint Thomas, Apostle of modernity” is inclined to blame philosophy of the 16th century and especially Descartes for “treason of reason for its highest purpose” without noticing the symbolism of the name of his own work. He believed that it was then when “.. .the internal hierarchy of the virtues of reason collapsed, philosophy separated from theology in order to claim the title of higher science, and the mathematical study of the sensual world and its phenomena began to crowd metaphysics, the human mind began to talk about its independence in relation to God and to being...” [21]. However, it is problematic to categorically agree with such conclusions today. If the destruction of the hierarchy can be viewed as a condition for the emergence of new historical conditions, later called Modernity, then ignoring the mental revolution that took place in scholastic philosophy, which, in the end, led to this destruction, looks today completely unjustified. It was within the framework of high scholasticism where a new gnoseological approach to creation has been formulated and the result of which such a reality as “nature” It is very useful in this context the work of Anatoly Akhutin dedicated to the genesis of a contempo-rary understanding of “nature” and its difference from the ancient “physis” in this context. See more: [23].was discovered, mind gained the opportunity to look at the world as a picture (using Heideggerian terminology), which resulted in the discovery of an interaction (cognition) method with the surrounding reality and adequate to the new realities.
Throughout the Middle Ages, the debate about the nature of universals did not abate; it can be schematically represented as a continuation of the struggle of Aristotelism against Platonism, in the end of which the peripatetics won.
For the Platonic tradition, the process of knowledge is associated with the contemplation of the world of ideas that are substantial in nature. Sensuality can add nothing to this knowledge, and the material world itself appears as contingent and accidental. This maxim of the ancient worldview is perfectly reflected in the work of st. Augustine: “All that bodily senses achieve, that they call sensual, never cease to change. Whether hair grows on our head, the body ages or blooms with youth, this happens in constant becoming, which is never interrupted. But that which is not, cannot be comprehended. Indeed, to comprehend means to understand scientifically, but one cannot understand something which does not cease to change. Therefore, one cannot hope that bodily senses will deliver us the truth in its purity” (cit. to: [22, p. 319]). Matthew of Aqua Sparta concisely formulated the main ethos of this approach, indicating that not things, but ideas are the cause of our knowledge, and if God had captured the form of ideas in our mind, as he did in the case of angels, we would know things as we know now.
Representatives of the same tradition, however, in this matter, already following Plotinus more, were forced to recognize the fundamental unknowability of God. As Plotinus once wrote about the One, showing that the maximum on which the human mind can count is to know that it is not the One, and not what it is. Similarly, representatives of apathic theology denied the possibility of obtaining any positive knowledge about God.
It would seem that this approach fits perfectly into the Christian worldview and is not only based on the ancient tradition, but also on the Holy Scripture, and therefore should not be revised. However, during the period of scholasticism, the opposite approach became the main one, within the framework of which the world of new meanings was born.
Paradoxically, it is also completely orthodox and no less grounded from the point of view of the Scripture than Platonic-Augustinian is. On the one hand, it can be described as a struggle for the recognition of the value of creation The disciple of Gilson and the scientific director Karol Wojtyla, the recognized expert on the phi-losophy of Thomas Aquinas Stefan Swiezawski noted that Aquinas did enough to defeat sacralism, accord-ing to which prayer, service, fasting, etc. has a higher status than ordinary work. “...Each question is sacred in its own way -- sacredly everything, wrote Swiezawski ,Analyzing the philosophy of St. Thomas. -- There are no divisions into sacred and non-sacred. Everything is sacred, and this is the true position of true sacral-ism. Recall here the words of St. Paul: “So, whether you eat, drink, or whatever you do, do everything to the glory of God” (1 Cor. 10.31) [24]. and, in this case, st. Francis' “Little Flowers” or Aquinas' “Summa Theologica” personify one semantic field: creation is the work of God and therefore is not something that should be avoided. On the other hand, to present it as an attempt of seeking hearts to know the Lord at least by analogy, and therefore the evidence of the existence of God at this time became almost an independent genre.
Albertus Magnus, Thomas Aquinas, Duns Scotus, William of Ockham, while developing a new methodology, discover the heuristic character of sensory knowledge. As Gilson notes in “The Spirit of Medieval Philosophy”, after realizing the danger of skepticism emanating from the Platonic concept of knowledge, medieval thought “had nothing left but to rehabilitate the sensual order; this is exactly what was to be done first by St. Thomas Aquinas, then by Duns Scot” [22, p. 324]. Aquinas indicates that the human soul occupies the lowest place among intelligent substances and, like angels, does not possess knowledge of truth by nature, and is therefore capable of knowing only on the basis of private things, through feelings In this question, and especially regarding the distinction between human and Divine knowledge, there is one interesting and one of the most in-depth studies on the philosophy of Thomas Aquinas, which came out recently, which belongs to the American researcher Eleonore Stump [25].. Here's what Swiezawski writes about the philosophy of St. Thomas: “Sensual knowledge here on earth, in our earthly conditions, determines mental knowledge” [24].
Aquinas asks a question about the connection of the eternal and the transient in our knowledge and responds as follows: “So these two kinds, namely the eternal and the transitory, are connected with our knowledge in such a way that each of them serves as a means for knowing the other. Thus, by reasoning, from knowledge of the transient we arrive at the knowledge of the eternal, for, according to the apostle, “the invisible through the viewing of creations is visible” (Romans 1: 20) [17, p. 109]. Basing on the canonical text of Scripture, Thomas Aquinas substantiates the possibility of knowing God through His creations, thus giving the creation a new unprecedented status of the apodictic element of God-knowledge. As Frederick Copleston notes: knowledge becomes anticipation of the vision of God in heaven. From this principle there is only one step to the modern natural science: it is necessary to stop the transcendental level, giving natural knowledge an independent status, and the mind will acquire a new (modern) form that it can apply to the new reality -- nature Describing the process of overcoming Platonic skepticism undertaken by the great scholastics, Gil-son wrote: “The only way out of the difficulty lies, therefore, in recognizing: there is empirical certainty based on inference with a stress put on experience. Undoubtedly, the induction of patterns from experi-ence will not lead us to absolutely necessary conclusions: there is no contradiction in the fact that things can be generated in a different way than they are actually produced. But the knowledge that we have about their laws will not be less reliable and infallible because it relies on the stability and necessity of the natures themselves. The great principle, which guarantees the value of experienced knowledge, says that everything that happens regularly, due to some reason that does not act freely, is a natural consequence of this reason. `Natural' means: not appropriate, but necessary. Therefore, the knowledge of nature, which we are able to acquire through experience, has the necessary character” [22, p. 331].. Rudolf Steiner in his lectures on tomism, appreciating the great merit of this tradition in opposition to nominalism, with which he associated the regress of the West, nevertheless said: “The problem that was previously solved by clairvoyance, by means of supersensory perceptions, has now descended into the sphere of thought, into the sphere of activity of the mind. This is the essence of the philosophy of Albert the Great and the philosophy of Thomas Aquinas...” [26].
Franciscan Duns Scotus developed in parallel to Dominican way and came to even more radical conclusions. Starting from the same passage from the Epistle to the Romans of Saint Paul and relying on the Augustinian legacy, Duns Scotus insists that invisible ideas are learned on the basis of creations, respectively, and their cognition (of creations) is of decisive importance. By virtue of a person's lack of the ability to know the truth in itself, he must constantly resort to the help of reason in order to find it. This is how the methodology looks like according to Duns Scotus: “.the human wanderer contemplates the essence of the stone, which for the divine mind is incommensurable and eternal, but he does not see it as eternal and incommensurable, [what it is] in relation to the divine mind, because it does not see its relationship to the divine mind, by virtue of which it is immutable; and he [a person] sees in this object the truth of an object and all that it contains virtually, through a rational study conducted in relation to this object» [2, p. 371]. And in the treatise “On the Knowability of God," he deciphers how this knowledge should be carried out: “The philosopher in Book III about the Soul says:“ Images for the mind are perceived as feelings ”. But the feeling feels nothing but the sensed; therefore, the mind does not know anything, besides, the images of which it can acquire through feelings» [2, p. 399].
William of Ockham on this matter has advanced even further, he is convinced, as indeed many thinkers before him, that only universals one can know; only he refuses them of any substantiality. The British thinker in his treatise “On Universals” explicitly writes that “a universal is a spoken word” [27, p. 119], and in the treatise “The fact that a universal is not a thing outside the soul” substantiates the position that “no universal is any substance that exists outside the soul.” [27, p. 119]. It follows from this that universals (ideas) have no substantiveness, and therefore no independent existence, independent from the knowing subject. On the contrary, the universal is a product of abstraction, the selection of quidditas, which produces the human mind, and this is where their (uni- versals) universality lies. “There are no such objects as“ man in general ”or“ humanity, ”writes medieval philosopher and translator of the works of the English Franciscan into Russian, A. Appolonov, concerning U. Ockham's philosophy, -- the general is“ mental image ”(fictum) or“ act of thinking "(actusintelligendi) and does not exist outside of human consciousness” [27, p. XV]. Universals are not separate substances of the world of ideas, but derivatives of human thinking. In the same treatise, Ockham writes: “. the statement exists only in the mind or in written or spoken words. But this is not a private substance. So it is clear that no statement can be made up of substances; but the statement is composed of universals; therefore, universals are not substances in any way possible” [27, p. 123]. Thus, a completely logical connection is built. Universals are not substances, but only a word, a product of abstraction, material for “extracting” quidditas, getting this extract, which provides an empirical world, cognizable by sensuality, respectively, to find the truth, you should pay maximum attention to empirical studies that form the basis of genuine knowledge.
An analysis of the texts of representatives of high scholasticism shows that it was during this period, on the one hand, that a new region of reality was discovered and substantiated -- “nature”, which was initially used exclusively for orthodox purposes of God- knowledge; on the other hand, a new type of mind was formed, adequate to this dimension of reality, which, after detranscendence, has been carried out in the philosophy of New Time, will become an independent system-forming entity In this regard, see also PiamaGaydenko's study on the influence of medieval nominalism on the development of the science of the New Age [29]..
Thetranscendenceofthefoundationsoftheclassicmind
Proceeding from the fact that for the classical mind the intellect is not a unique result of evolution which characterizes the crown of its development -- a man, but an ontological (cosmic) essence, manifested in the human race with the least intensity, its bases are of transcendental nature. Appealing to various classical texts, it is not difficult to show that the origins of the pre-modern mind are transcendental (in the pre-Kantian sense of the term). The individual, potential human mind is able to act only because there is a universal actual mind, which does not only give being to the private minds but is also a rule-maker for them and is itself nothing more than a manifestation of the Good (Plato), an emanation of the One (Plotinus), a manifestation of God (Christian philosophy).
This tradition can be traced from Plato, who, for example, in “Phaedo” considers what makes beautiful beautiful, makes reasonable reasonable, etc. “Look, what will come next,” said Socrates, “will it seem so to you, like to me? It seems to me that if there is something beautiful besides beautiful in itself, then it is beautiful for nothing but its participation in that beautiful. I say the same about everything. Do you agree with this reason? “I agree”, he answered, “Plato writes [28, p. 170-171]. This is just a sample of the study by the ancient Greek philosopher of his main concept -- the theory of the true world of ideas. But at the same time, it is the legitimization of the maxim, which will become the commonplace of all the predominant philosophies about the transcendental dimension as the true cause of the immanent world.
From this point of view it is quite logical that the closer human thinking (action) is to the divine, the more perfect it is. This type of transcendentalism is well noticed by A. Losev. Analyzing the philosophy of Aristotle, the Russian-Soviet thinker pointed out the apodic- tic connection of the individual mind and the divine: “But if this is so, then the potential presence of mind in a person must be required to recognize the existence of the mind as a whole, regardless of man, mind as such. And if the mind contains only potentially in a person, but actually if it manifests itself and doesn't also, then there is also a mind that is always relevant, infinitely relevant" [4, p. 44]. The meaning of what has been said is quite clear and does not require additional comments. It is only worth noting that this thought of Aristotle will be a very popular Christian philosophy and especially scholasticism.
Plotinus in his “Enneads” repeatedly illustrates the same thought about the transcendental basis of the functioning of individual minds. The extract from the second treatise “On the birth of being” VI “Ennead” is as follows: “Mind is beyond [private] minds, it directs individual minds, it is their strength [= opportunity], it possesses them in their universality. And, again, all minds in their partialness have a universal Mind, just as private knowledge contains knowledge [as such And in the treatise “On the mind, ideas and existence” of the fifth “Ennead” Plotinus writes: “Beauty arises in the soul through reason. Then: what is that which the mind gives to the soul? With necessity -- Mind, but not the mind that is sometimes clever, and sometimes stupid, but the true Mind” [14, p. 262].]” [30, p. 145]. Simply put: the human mind is the weak counterpart of the Mind of the Divine, that is acting as a transcendental condition for the action of private minds.
...Ïîäîáíûå äîêóìåíòû
The value of art in one's life, his role in understanding the characteristics of culture. The skill and ability of the artist to combine shapes and colors in a harmonious whole. Create an artist of her unique style of painting, different from the others.
ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [2,3 M], äîáàâëåí 20.10.2013Customs and traditions, national and religious holidays, the development of art and architecture in Turkey. Description of the relationship of Turks to the family, women, marriage, birth and burial. Characteristics of the custom of Sunnet - circumcision.
ðåôåðàò [28,1 K], äîáàâëåí 21.01.2012The development of painting in the USA. The First American Revolution and the young republic. Landscape, history and marine painting. American Museum of Natural History. National Gallery of Art. Leslie Lohman Gay Art Foundation, the Philips Collection.
êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [74,6 K], äîáàâëåí 12.02.2014The study brief biography and works of the great artist Isaac Levitan. The most famous artwork is gorgeous landscape. A photographic image of the famous master of nature, landscapes of Russian nature, drawings, watercolors and book illustrations.
ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [789,2 K], äîáàâëåí 13.03.2015St. Valentine's Day is the traditional day on which lovers. The day's associations with romantic love. History of Valentine's Day. The influential Gnostic teacher Valentinius: versions of these legends. Valentine's Day in USA and other cultures.
ðåôåðàò [11,2 K], äîáàâëåí 31.01.2010The history of the emergence of Hollywood in the central region of Los Angeles, USA. Education on this territory of the first film studios and film industry. "Walk of Fame" and especially its creation. The use of science for the production of films.
ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [6,5 M], äîáàâëåí 18.12.2014Introduction to the history of the Steinway piano - an uncompromising standard of sound, beauty and investment value. History and development of the company Steinway & Sons. The study of competitiveness, strengths and weaknesses of the marketing company.
ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [565,2 K], äîáàâëåí 04.05.2012Theatre in British history as an integral part of the cultural heritage. Stages of professional development of the theater from the first theater and the trivial to the most modern experimental projects. Famous people of British theater for centuries.
êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [58,6 K], äîáàâëåí 06.12.2013Seven wonders of Ukraine: National Dendrological park "Sofiivka", Kievo-Pechers’ka Lavra. Ancient Greek town Khersones Tavriisky (Chersonesos) - the city founded by Greek colonists, more than two or a half thousand years ago in south-western Crimea.
ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [888,1 K], äîáàâëåí 12.05.2011The concept of "intercultural dialogue". The problem of preserving the integrity nations and their cultural identity. formation of such a form of life, as cultural pluralism, which is an adaptation to a foreign culture without abandoning their own.
ñòàòüÿ [108,6 K], äîáàâëåí 12.11.2012Holiday celebrations in America signify the rich blending of historic traditions from other cultures with the uniquely commemorative nature of the people of the United States. Brief review and description basic national and ethnic holidays of Americans.
êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [42,3 K], äîáàâëåí 02.04.2013Japan is a constitutional monarchy where the power of the Emperor is very limited. Òhe climate and landscape of the country. Formation of language and contemporary trends, religious trends. Household and national traditions. Gender Roles in Japan.
êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [48,1 K], äîáàâëåí 08.04.2015Rockers have emerged as a subculture in the fifties- sixties, in the era of rock'n'roll. Features of clothes style, a hairdress also are necessary attributes of the real rocker. Rockers wear leather motorcycle jacket adorned with an abundance of buttons.
ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [10,8 M], äîáàâëåí 21.03.2012Turko-Iranian-Muslim element is a integral part of India. Integration of the Mughal regime in Indian society. The theme of paradise in the decorative arts. Features of the mausoleum of Humayun which became samples in construction of monuments of Mughal.
ñòàòüÿ [17,1 K], äîáàâëåí 18.05.2013Sumer as one of the oldest centers of civilization, situated between the rivers Tigris and Euphrates. Historical evidence of contact with aliens. Persuasion Sumerians of death as a natural transition into eternity. The history of invention of cuneiform.
ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [920,5 K], äîáàâëåí 29.12.2011Louvre - the biggest and most famous art museum, built in 1190 by King Philippe Auguste as a fortress against the Vikings. The history of the Louvre, the description of the exhibits: paintings, sculptures and artifacts collected over the five centuries.
ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [714,8 K], äîáàâëåí 16.09.2012History of creation. The two-act ballet "the Nutcracker" was ordered to Tchaikovsky by the Directorate of the Imperial theatres in early 1891. Step 1. Picture 1. Overture. The decoration and lighting of the Christmas tree. The Appearance Of Drosselmeyer.
ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [3,4 M], äîáàâëåí 04.12.2016The Victoria and Albert Museum. Bomb damage on the exhibition road facade. The Victorian period. The John Madejski Garden. Queen Victoria and Prince Albert Love Story. The History of the Tower of London. Buckingham Palace, Albert Hall, Trafalgar Square.
ðåôåðàò [39,1 K], äîáàâëåí 09.02.2012James Cameron is famous canadian film director, screenwriter, producer, and researcher of the underwater world. James Cameron's filmography includes five financial records. Interesting Facts of life and work of film director. History of the personal life.
ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [3,3 M], äîáàâëåí 21.10.2014The Brooklyn Bridge is a popular landmark in the New York City. The History and the Structure of the Brooklyn Bridge. The Bridge and American Culture. Ethnic and foreign responses to America, nationalism, memory, commemoration, popular culture.
ðåôåðàò [13,1 K], äîáàâëåí 09.07.2013