Rawls’s theory of international justice: a brief reconstruction and critical commentary

The aim of this paper is to offer a concise and faithful account of Rawls’ theory of international justice, in an effort, first, to elucidate the structure of the argument that is advanced in that theory and second, to present a critical assessment of it.

Рубрика Государство и право
Вид статья
Язык английский
Дата добавления 31.08.2023
Размер файла 37,4 K

Отправить свою хорошую работу в базу знаний просто. Используйте форму, расположенную ниже

Студенты, аспиранты, молодые ученые, использующие базу знаний в своей учебе и работе, будут вам очень благодарны.

Размещено на http://www.allbest.ru

Rawls's theory of international justice: a brief reconstruction and critical commentary

Charilaos Stampoulis

Теорія міжнародної справедливості Роулза: коротка реконструкція та критичний коментар

Харілаос Стампуліс

Анотація

Мета цієї статті -- запропонувати стислий і достовірний виклад теорії міжнародної справедливості Роулза, намагаючись, по-перше, з'ясувати структуру аргументу, який висувається в цій теорії, і, по-друге, дати критичну оцінку це. Розділ про критичну оцінку намагається, з одного боку, впоратися з ключовими методологічними питаннями, які мають більш загальне відношення до загальної політичної філософської позиції Ролза, включаючи конструктивістську перспективу створення теорії та поділ між політичною концепцією та комплексною доктриною; з іншого боку, зважити низку суттєвих тверджень, висунутих у теорії міжнародної справедливості Роулза, включаючи визнання народів основними суб'єктами міжнародного права, толерантне ставлення до так званих порядних людей і досить тонке тлумачення права людини, закріплені в Законі народів. У статті зроблено спробу навести низку причин, які могли б добре підходити для пояснення сумнівів її автора щодо обґрунтованості теоретичної точки зору Роулза щодо як її формальних методологічних особливостей, так i 6ільш орієнтованих на зміст переконань.

Ключові слова: філософія права, політична філософія, права людини, Ролз.

Abstract

international justice critical

The aim of this paper is to offer a concise and faithful account of Rawls' theory of international justice, in an effort, first, to elucidate the structure of the argument that is advanced in that theory and, second, to present a critical assessment of it. The critical assessment section attempts, on the one hand, to cope with crucial methodological issues, which have a more general bearing upon Rawls's overall political philosophical position, including the constructivist perspective of theory making and the division between a political conception and a comprehensive doctrine; on the other hand, to weigh up a set of substantive claims made in the Rawlsian theory of international justice including the recognition of peoples as the fundamental subjects of international law, the toleration of the so-called decent peoples and the considerably thin construal of human rights encompassed in The Law of Peoples. The paper attempts to provide a series of reasons that could be well- suited to explicate its author's doubts about the soundness of the Rawlsian theoretical perspective with regard to both its formal methodological features and its more content-oriented convictions.

Keywords: philosophy of law, political philosophy, human rights, Rawls.

Introduction

Few topics of Rawls' complex and multifaceted moral and political thought have ever been more inviting to dissatisfaction and criticism than his theory of international justice. Drawing on major issues, as the condensed list of rights demanding protection at the international level, or the absence, not only of a globally applicable «difference principle» but also of any global distributive principle at all, a legion of thinkers have doubted the status of Rawls's international law theory as an appropriate extension of his domestic theory of justice. A source of ongoing controversy is, furthermore, his determination to recognize the peoples as the principal actors and ultimate bearers of right at the global stage of social interaction, not to mention his inclusion of the so called «decent peoples» as equal members of the global society. In that regard, the aim of this paper is to take up a brief reconstruction of the Rawlsian views on the topic of international justice, in an effort to appreciate, at a second stage, their argumentative force in relation to the aforementioned, by and large, issues without disregarding for an in passing commentary of some other debatable matters.

The Law of Peoples in outline

Rawls' The Law of Peoples, a work belonging to the later period of the philosopher's career, purports to put forth «a particular political conception of right and justice that applies to the principles and norms of international law and practice». Rawls John. The Law of Peoples with the Idea of Public Reason Revisited. Harvard University Press, 2001. P.3. (hereafter LoP). ThomasW. Pogge locates the central difference between the domestic and the international law in that in the domestic case some matters are nonnegotiable, «for example, that none will be slaves or be left to starve», whereas in the international arena «the dominant assumption-and well-grounded fear-is that everything is negotiable, that any law, treaty, charter, or declaration may be reinterpreted, violated, renegotiated, abrogated, abandoned, or simply forgotten». See Thomas W. Pogge. Realizing Rawls. Cornell University Press, 1989, P.228. The compliance with the ideals and principles ingredient in this conception of international law is about to establish a «Society of Peoples», well-suited to put an end to political injustice, which is the main root of the great evils of human history, «unjust war and oppression, religious persecution and the denial of liberty of conscience, starvation and poverty, [...] genocide and mass murder» LoP. P. 6-7. etc. Accordingly, the particular content of the ideals and principles that must be introduced for the regulation of the global society «might be developed out of a liberal idea of justice similar to, but more general than, the idea» LoP. P. 3. Rawls labels «justice as fairness».

A conception of justice is fair on the condition that the procedure that engenders it is similarly fair, that is, the parties called upon to agree on principles of justice are afforded a fundamentally equal status by virtue of their shared capacity to have a sense of justice and a conception of the good. In his Reason and Justice, State University of New York Press, 1988, P. 107, Richard Dien Winfield appropriately remarks that «like the traditional social contract, the original position would forfeit its foundational role as the exclusive source of the principles of justice if its choice procedure were at all predicated upon any prior virtues, idea of the good, or rights and duties». In this regard, Rawls is guilty of inconsistency because «the rationale for the veil of ignorance lies [...] in a prior assumption that justice is fairness, where fairness is understood to consist in treating individuals equally in respect to their capacity as choosing selves, without regard for any other differences between them». The possession of this twofold capacity makes persons reasonable and rational respectively. The equal participants to this hypothetical and nonhistorical social contract procedure are, according to Rawls, neither individual persons nor states, but peoples, which are ideotypically seen as falling into five major categories: reasonable liberal peoples, decent peoples, outlaw states, societies burdened by unfavorable conditions, benevolent absolutisms. Among them, only liberal and decent people meet in an adequate way the criteria to qualify for the Rawlsian normative ideal of well-orderedness.

The arrangements that have to be in place at the international level for the sake of global justice, peace and stability ought to take seriously into consideration the empirical condition of «reasonable pluralism», a term Rawls employs in his Political Liberalism to describe the cardinal predicament of modern liberal democratic societies, being now extended to the global domain where comprehensive doctrinal diversity is regarded to be even more excessive, due to peoples» «different cultures and traditions of thought, both religious and nonreligious». LoP. P. 11. A liberal political conception of global justice seeks to alleviate the potentially dissolutive consequences of the unregulated international pluralism, setting the stage for an all the more cohesive «Society of Peoples», an ideal larded with realistic and utopian features at the same time.

A liberal political conception of global justice is realistic, on the one hand, to the degree that it is not incompatible with the natural laws and the objective facts about human nature that can be deduced by them; on the other hand, to the extent that its contents «are workable and applicable to ongoing political and social arrangements». LoP. P. 13. It is, respectively, utopian, in that its contents are expected to «specify a reasonable and just society»; LoP. P. 14. that is, a conception, or a family of conceptions, conducive to the building of a global society that honors basic rights and liberties, assigns special priority to them over other social concerns, grants «primary goods» for substantial and effective worth to be imparted to the basic rights and liberties and satisfies the «criterion of reciprocity» between equal, free and reasonable social agents. Other requirements for a realistic utopian conception of global justice are the following:

it must lean on a construal of the political as a «free-standi- ng» domain of public practical discourse, insulated from the Babel of «comprehensive doctrines»;

it must result in the establishment of an institutional framework capable of inculcating into the social actors the sense of justice and the virtue of political cooperation for the sake of «stability for the right reasons» (following from the agents' sense of justice and conception of the good, i.e., their reasonableness and rationality, respectively);

it must receive affirmation by an «overlapping consensus of comprehensive doctrines», See Mandle Jon. Rawls' A Theory of Justice. Cambridge University Press, 2009. P. 147. so that social unity and stability would not be the outcome of an external and mechanical political compromise, as it is the case, for instance, with Hobbes;

it must constitutively enclose a reasonable idea of political toleration.

As already mentioned, Rawls asserts, in familiar, traditional contractual terms, that the content of the political conception of international justice is to be reached via a procedure of construction, RexMartin and DavidA.Reidy offer a lucid description of a constructivist conception of justice, which «represents the principles of justice not as part of some timeless and mind-independent moral order known through theoretical reason, but rather as an outcome of a procedure of construction rooted in practical rather than theoretical reasoning. Practical reason concerns the production of objects in accord with a particular conception of them. If our practical task is to produce a just society, we need practical principles to guide us in this undertaking. These we construct through a procedure that models both the noncontroversial empirical facts that constrain our undertaking as well as our shared understandings of the ingredient ideals of persons, fair social cooperation, well-orderedness, and so on. These ideals we draw from our moral and political self-understanding as practical moral agents. Whether the outcome of our procedure of construction, our tentatively selected conception of justice, is correct or not is not a function of its truth theoretically assessed, but rather of its reasonableness practically assessed. We have correctly identified the principles of justice if after due to reflection they are in wide reflective equilibrium with our other considered convictions. If they are, they mark the practically correct way for us to make together the just society we jointly desire. There is no further court of appeal beyond our shared practical reason». See their Introduction in Rawls' Law of Peoples, A Realistic Utopia?, ed. RexMartin and DavidA.Reidy, Blackwell Publishing 2006, P. 11. invoking once again, at this level, the idea of the «original position» and its attendant idea of the «veil of ignorance». Still, other than the construction of principles at the domestic level, the representatives of parties in this particular connection do not represent individual persons, as was the case with the domestic original position, but rather peoples, who act through their governments. Thus, in contrast with his domestic individualism, Rawls seems, to the discomfort of his liberal cosmopolitan readers, to subscribe to a, more or less, communitarian position in his international law theory, even though he resists the conservative realism of viewing the international arena as inescapably inhabited by and regulated on the basis of traditional political states.

The expressed reason for this maneuver is that the peoples are much more prone to act morally, namely, in a peaceful and respectful of human rights manner, in stark contrast with the, by definition, self-interested and trigger-happy character of the political states. In this regard, the people are deemed to be to a greater degree inclined to restrict their formal autonomy and arbitrary self-centeredness, abiding by the norms of international law to the benefit of global peace and stability, whereas the states, traditionally conceived in their irreducible sovereignty, are not realistically expected to do so.

Peoples, in general, are considered by Rawls as collective entities, the members of which are tightly connected by virtue of strong cultural and historical bonds, like common traditions, common historical past, common language etc. The liberal peoples, even in the differentiated variety of liberal doctrines they happen to espouse, figure as the most just, reasonable and well-ordered representatives of the global medley of peoples. The next lower position on this normative climax is reserved for «decent peoples», on the premise that their protection of human rights, their reluctance to carry out unjust wars, their commitment to a common good conception of politics, their provisions for basic liberties (though not the full set of liberal ones) allows for the inclusion of the notion of decency into the normative guiding framework of the international system of cooperation, even though the normative force of decency is much weaker and of lesser value for a political conception of global justice compared with the notion of liberal reasonableness.

The rest of the possible types of peoples, namely, outlaw states, burdened societies and benevolent absolutisms are, on Rawls' account, very far from satisfying the criteria of liberal reasonableness or decency, being under the sway of a multitude of adverse factors afflicting their political culture and institutions in many respects. They are, therefore, unsuited for membership in the international «Society of Peoples».

The notion of the «original position» at the international level is deployed as a model of fair representation for the reasonable peoples, liberal and decent. Under the «veil of ignorance» the representatives are denied access to a great deal of particularities characterizing their peoples. They ignore, for instance, the comprehensive doctrines, the extent of the natural resources, the level of the economic development, «the size of the territory, or the population, or the relative strength of the people whose fundamental interests they represent». LoP. P. 32. This is a formal condition employed to safeguard impartiality and foreclose the possibility for a biased outcome of the deliberative procedure.

Since the norms and principles ultimately to be agreed upon are intended to be component parts of a strictly political and not comprehensive conception of justice, the process of their identification is imperative to be conducted without appeal to any particular philosophical, moral or religious ideas, but only to the «various fundamental ideas drawn from the public political culture of a democratic society». Ibid. Only reasons that derive from the public political culture of a democratic society are, to Rawls' mind, relevant to the procedural workings of the original position, as enabling factors of a «political conception of justice that can be the focus of an overlapping consensus and thereby serve as a public basis of justification in a society marked by the fact of reasonable pluralism». Ibid.

In so far as the political conception of global justice is uncovered through a rational consideration of the norms inherent to the public political culture of a democratic society, its content is anything but unfamiliar and adventitious. Rather, it is seen by Rawls to frame principles deep-seated within the political culture of the modern world. In the general absence of systematic deductive processes in Rawls' philosophical methodology, the resulting principles of international justice are not regarded as definite and are placed in an order of mere enumeration:

peoples are to be respected as free and independent in their reciprocal relations;

they are to observe treaties and undertakings;

they are equal parties to the agreements that bind them;

they are to observe a duty of nonintervention;

they have the right of self-defense but no right to instigate war for reasons other than self-defense;

they are to honor human rights;

they are to observe certain specified restrictions in the conduct of war;

they have duty to assist other peoples living under unfavorable conditions that prevent their having a just or decent political and social regime.

These principles are and must be open to different formulations and interpretations, which is actually the main task to be carried out by the representatives of the peoples. Moreover, the political conception of global justice is to encompass additional principles «for forming and regulating federations (associations) of peoples, and standards of fairness for trade and other cooperative institutions». LoP. P.38. On the ground of this, or maybe another comparable set of reasonable liberal principles, the global society attains to its specific public reason, which is the ultimate guiding framework for the evaluation and justification of any particular social and political normative claims made by peoples at the international level.

The liberal political conception of global justice expounded so far in outline belongs to the first part of the ideal theory, «Ideal theory asks which principles of justice would regulate a perfectly (or nearly perfectly) just society, that is [...] well-ordered. Nonideal theory in turn asks which principles to adopt under less happy conditions when perfect justice is, at best, a distant goal». See Stemplowska Z., Swift A. Rawls on Ideal and Nonideal Theory. A Companion to Rawls / ed. JonMandle, DavidA.Reidy. Wiley-Blackwell, 2014. P.112. The topics included in the nonideal theory are the theory of punishment, the doctrine of just war, the justification of various ways of opposition to unjust regimes etc. according to the architectonics of The Law of Peoples. In the second part of the ideal theory Rawls introduces and elaborates on the notion of the toleration of nonliberal peoples, laying out arguments for the extension of the liberal international law to decent hierarchical peoples, as he calls them. The case is made by means of an analogy with the domestic level. Namely, to the same extent that the principles of domestic justice are addressed, through the basic structure of domestic society, to the citizens, regardless of their reasonable comprehensive doctrines, the norms of international law are addressed to the peoples, no matter of their even more diversified and conflicting reasonable comprehensive doctrines. Given that the only kind of peoples, apart from the liberal democratic ones, who partially satisfy the social, institutional and political criteria to be counted as reasonable, are the decent peoples, the liberal political conception of justice is extended to them alike. Indeed, the conception in question has been sketched by Rawls in notably minimal terms, so as to be fitting to be agreed upon by decent peoples too, on the fairly realistic assumption that the cultural background of those peoples (think of an Islamic society for example) figures as an unfavorable condition for their endorsing a fuller set of liberal democratic ideals, unless this was made by external force and imperialistic intervention on the part of liberal democratic peoples. But such an intolerant attitude is highly undesirable for Rawls, on the presumption that it would infringe on the equality, self-respect and self-determination of the decent peoples. After all, decent peoples, besides a large portion of other acceptably reasonable features of their background justice, pay due respect to human rights, which is the supreme normative criterion of international toleration for Rawls.

However, the conception of human rights enveloped in the «public reason» of the «Society of Peoples» as the ultimate arbiter of claims on war and toleration is, on par with the overall political conception of justice at this level, particularly weak from the perspective of the standard liberal mindset, in as much as it is incommensurate with the richer class of human rights enjoyed by the citizens of a constitutional democratic regime at the domestic level. In fact, what must count as intolerable in the international interaction, not only permitting but also dictating political, if not armed intervention in the internal affairs and external policy of other peoples, otherwise autonomous, is the violation of a considerably condensed list of human rights, which Rawls classifies as «urgent rights». These may include «freedom from slavery and serfdom, liberty (but not equal liberty) of conscience, and security of ethnic groups from mass murder and genocide».LoP. P. 79. The upshot at this point is that the notion of human rights is rendered a subset of the more extended and demanding class of rights that is normally protected by the legal systems of constitutional democracies, in a pragmatically propelled attempt to relax the normative qualifications for membership in the «Society of Peoples», so that illiberal but decent peoples are not excluded, which would be to the detriment of global stability.

When it comes to the nonideal theory, or the more empirically-centered theory of noncompliance or only partial compliance with the mandates of the political conception of global justice that is ideally set forth as the supreme standard of international lawfulness, Rawls initially addresses the traditional issue of just war theory, accepting the right of resort to armed force only in the case of self-defense, or in the case of the violation of human rights, as already mentioned. Still, the exercise of the right to war is not unlimited or unqualified, but is subject to principles restricting the conduct of war, mostly concerning the rights of the noncombatants.

Furthermore, in reference to societies burdened by unfavorable cultural, institutional or financial conditions, Rawls goes at length to adduce supporting arguments to his rejection of a global application of the difference principle, or of any other kind of global distributive principle of justice. To the discomfort of many of his readers, who justifiably cry out the outrageous inequalities in the global distribution of income, Rawls instead proposes a more moderate remedy, via the less requiring «duty of assistance», which is the duty «to assist burdened societies to become full members of the Society of Peoples and to be able to determine the path of their own future for themselves». LoP. P. 118. Contrary to the difference principle or other distributive principles, the duty of assistance has a specific cut-off point designated by the assurance that the societies under assistance «have achieved just liberal or decent basic institutions». Ibid. Beyond this point, any supply of assistance, financial, institutional, technological, could be a paternalistic deviation that falls short of the respect owed to the political autonomy of societies burdened with unfavorable conditions.

In the concluding remarks to the Law of Peoples and in response to the objection that the proffered political conception of global justice is hopelessly western-centered and actually at odds with its intended universal reach, Rawls pinpoints that, as it is the case also with the notion of human rights, the liberal political conception of international justice is not necessarily peculiar to western culture, but objectively valid. In consistency with his overall argumentative tactics, the epistemological claim on objectivity is not here, once again, advanced on the comprehensive grounds of philosophical epistemology. What is instead appealed to as the proper standard for objectivity to be measured by is whether the liberal political conception of global justice «satisfies the criterion of reciprocity and belongs to the public reason of the Society of liberals and decent Peoples». LoP. P. 121. On this weaker, noncomprehensive account of objectivity, the criterion of reciprocity confers universal validity in the sense that it represents the sine qua non condition of minimal social cooperation at any level, while the notion of public reason is invoked as the appropriate politically-oriented epistemological antidote in a pluralistic world actually occupied by a large number of competing epistemological doctrines.

Elements of a critical commentary of The Law of Peoples

Rethinking the distinction between the political and the comprehensive

In the light of this sketchy reconstruction of the Rawlsian theory of international justice, I shall now proceed to lay out a series of critical remarks bearing in mind that any faithful and fair assessment at this point should, first of all, be reminiscent of the fact that this work is not primarily patterned upon the strong theoretical claims of the classic A Theory of Justice, but rather upon the weaker ones of the Political Liberalism. The latter work largely emerged from Rawls' growing discontent with the Theory's «congruence argument», which attempted to demonstrate the objective compatibility and necessary connection of the conception of justice as fairness with the good of the individual persons and the intrinsic worth of their converging with that principle of conduct.See Freeman S. Rawls. Routledge, 2007. P. 315-322. The optimistic view being held there, namely, that the principle of justice as fairness, by virtue of its more or less objective harmony with the autonomous moral nature of the individual persons, would come to be widely approved by them, even more on the premises just delineated, was about to decisively change during the next decades, once Rawls were to take more seriously into account the fact of «reasonable pluralism».

More exactly, Rawls progressively came to the pressing for him awareness that in a modern pluralistic society, where freedom of conscience, expression and association are institutionally secured, a little consensus is to be expected over the definition of the good, since in such a society the individual persons actually endorse many different «comprehensive doctrines», which, in fact, embrace many different, if not competing and conflicting conceptions of the good. What is thus needed for the practical applicability of the liberal norms of justice and the ensuing social stability is, to Rawls' mind, a merely «political conception» of justice appropriately configured to attain to an «overlapping consensus of comprehensive doctrines». Significantly, the consensus in question should indeed rely on reasons that are internal to the reasonable comprehensive doctrines advocated by individuals. The main reason for this provision is that the social stability thereby achieved would be firmer than just an externally and artificially accommodated modus vivendi.

This is not to say that Rawls ever came to cast doubt on his previous commitment to the notion of justice as fairness. Nevertheless, his change of perspective in the direction of the realistic concern regarding the possibility of the actual and consent-based enforcement of the principle of justice as fairness motivated a significant modification of the general sense of that principle for the sake of the removal of the comprehensive elements that stayed afflicting it as potential sources of disagreement with other comprehensive worldviews. In other words, the distinction drawn in the Political Liberalism and, by extension, in The Law of Peoples, between a neutral political conception of justice and a conception of justice articulated in terms of a comprehensive doctrine is predominantly attributable to the empirical contextualization of the principle of justice as fairness and the correlated prioritization of an inquiry into the prerequisites of a stable social unification under the precepts of a more minimal conception of liberal justice.

The aforementioned account may leave as with some puzzles to be solved (e.g., if a large majority of individual persons in a liberal democratic society are presupposed as accepting, for any reasons, the constitutional essentials of this society, why does the problem of stability loom so large in Rawls' account? Or, provided that the overlapping consensus rests on reasons interior to the several comprehensive doctrines, what is the reason for justification in terms of a political conception and the companion idea of public reason?), but it partially explains the strikingly condensed version of a modern conception of social justice to be implemented, according to The Law of Peoples, in the domain of international relations and within the theoretical framework of the Rawlsian distinction between the political and the comprehensive, particularly in the face of the truism that the global social and political stage is even more pluralistic than the domestic. But it is precisely that theoretical framework that I don't find adequately convincing.

As a matter of fact, one could ask for the underlying principle of the division of the political and the comprehensive, unless one resolves to distill it from merely contingent empirical considerations. For reasons of consistency, that principle must be political rather than comprehensive. However, that would condemn the explication and the justification of the division to a question-begging devoid of explanatory force. If, on the other hand, the division of the political and the comprehensive were deemed to be a comprehensive one, the priority of the political would be, incoherently, unsustainable. And, to my mind, this is at any rate the case.

To put it in slightly different terms, once «reasonableness» is rendered an attribute of a comprehensive conception that is in accord with the liberal democratic political conception of justice, then the thus construed standard of reasonableness cannot be met by the political conception of justice itself if the inconsistency of petitio principii is to be evaded. If, on the other hand, the reasonableness of the political conception is affirmed to derive from its correspondence with an objectively reasonable comprehensive doctrine, then the political conception's supposed function as the primary foundation of reasonableness has to be repudiated. Either way, the freestanding political conception of justice cannot account for the reasonableness it allegedly confers to the comprehensive doctrines that are in conformity to it.

Moreover, if, in line with the requirements of practicability, political legitimacy and social stability, an ample amount of comprehensive doctrines can actually qualify for a reasonable compliance with the liberal democratic conception of justice, even more from their own resources, then the appeal to a strictly political conception is made redundant. The liberal-oriented content of those comprehensive conceptions is, in that event, sufficient for the purpose of social unity, well-orderedness and stability, and no recourse to the «doctrinal autonomy» of a «free-standing» political conception is necessary. If, by contrast, there could be hardly any possibility for such compliance, then the political conception of justice as a commonly accepted denominator of just conduct would end up being a chimera.

Furthermore, provided that the liberal political conception is invoked to override controversial philosophical claims susceptible to ignite socially harmful disagreement, one might wonder if the content of the liberal political conception itself is burdened with controversy too, which cannot be dispelled by a simple reduction to the alleged neutrality of the political. After all, the liberal democratic political conception is certainly not the fruit of a self-contained evolution of the western political culture that has taken place in isolation from decisive reorientations in modern philosophical theory, not to mention religion, or other comprehensive cultural aspects. The pursuit of a political justification that holds no communion with the other constitutive parts of a wider cultural horizon is vain, in as much as the concept of the political is itself dubitable (e.g., Marxists would eagerly discard it), let alone the notion of justification as such, whose nature is a complex and highly debatable epistemological problem for one to pin his hopes on any common sense reasoning resting on the formal procedures of the political discourse.

This is even more the case as regards the claims on personal value, liberty, autonomy, democracy, equality, which represent notions inerasably charged with huge controversy, irrespective of whether they are subsumed to the category of the philosophical and comprehensive or the political. If these controversies were unlikely to be settled on philosophical grounds, their reduction to the political would fare no better, given that their normative content remained intact. A supporter of a comprehensive doctrine that casts doubt on the principles of a liberal democratic constitution is quite unlikely to agree and act at liberty upon just the same principles by virtue of their being robbed of any serious justification apart from their association with the presumably indubitable necessities of the political condition per se. On the contrary, if those controversies could be resolved by rational philosophical argument, which is what Rawls doubts, then it would be more appropriate, instead of consigning philosophical rationality to the formality of a political conception, to act the other way round and assign formality to the comprehensive views that fail to exhibit a rational content. In the same vein, a reply to the possible objection that that might injure the self-respect of those committed to those unfounded opinions could be that their self-respect is, in that regard, once again formal. By insuring the possibility of a «free-standing» sort of justification per se, Rawls is in essence taking this direction, though he should have insisted on locating it in the philosophical rather than the political.

The advantage of the philosophical over the political, in terms of doctrinal autonomy and exegetical independence, is that the conceptions developing within the former carry their fostering reasons within them, whereas the political conceptions, in the way Rawls construes them, either appear as accidental cultural stipulations, privileged in an ungrounded manner over any other political conceptions embedded in our political culture, or rather remain hostage to the heteronomy of the comprehensive justifications that constitute the overlapping consensus. Either way, the form of justification is stripped of its content and the content is stripped of its form. The remedy to this disruption is the promotion of a comprehensive philosophical account of justice, with the political conception being an indispensable constituent part of it. In this sense, the political domain is accorded a partial free-standingness, which lies in its role of supremely regulating and universally enforcing the whole system of justice. Nevertheless, it is at the same time part and parcel of a more thoroughly determined systematic conception of rationality that deserves to be considered as more perfectly free-standing in that it is liberated from unaccounted presuppositions and totally self-grounded by dialectically superseding the more abstract domains of morality and politics, while incorporating them as the constitutive building-blocks of its entirely concrete doctrinal autonomy. This is in outline the conception of rationality in work within Hegel's systematic philosophy. After all, the Rawlsian presupposition of persons' substantial allegiance towards the basic principles of the free modern world is clearly indicative of a considerable advance in our collective rationality, which has a huge effect on our traditional or other comprehensive doctrines, even the most illiberal and reactionary of them. Why should we not focus on the further development of the rational core implicit in these doctrines, rather than appealing to the problematic formalism definitive of the insulation of the political domain?

That could most probably bring about the desired legitimacy and stability, indeed for the right reasons, in accord with Rawls' prescription, and not for the often unfounded comprehensive reasons or the contingent politically determined reasons. With regard to the comprehensive doctrines, public reasoning would not be content with just bracketing and leaving intact their irrational dimensions on the condition that reasonable consent was given by them to the main set of principles informing the liberal democratic regime, but would predominantly prompt the acceleration of the cultural processes that would be most favorable for their gradual conversion. With respect, accordingly, to the political conception of justice, its justification would be rooted in stronger grounds than just relying on the immediacy of our «fundamental intuitive ideas» or on any given facts and features of social cooperation, whose empirical character would be an inappropriate basis for universal and necessary inferences, let alone judgments concerning the intrinsic value and worth of engaging in such cooperation.

Moreover, as regards the issue of toleration, its extent would then be determined by our substantially confident certainty about the stabilizing effects of our shared rationality leaving no room for compromising rationality by our formally confident appeal to the stabilizing effects of toleration. In the domestic case, where the proponents of comprehensive doctrines are presupposed by Rawls to grant sufficient consent to the essentials of the reasonable and rational conception of justice, this compromise is admittedly not so extensive as to shake the commitment to the universal appeal of the modern type of legitimizing moral and political claims in a decisive way. A full set of political liberties and their priority is insured, with the only compromise being the replacement of the possibly controversial, as for its consequences for the character of its attendant social and economic system «difference principle», with the less radical but more widely accepted constitutional provision for a social minimum income. Nevertheless, when it comes to the theory of the international norms of justice, the predication of the ideal of worldwide stability upon the formal equality, consent, self-respect, self-determination and toleration of those who refuse to abandon cultural and political practices incommensurate with the modern word results in an unnecessary shrinking of the western, fundamentally rooted in the concept of freedom, paradigm of political legitimation. This is evident in Rawls' proposals regarding the normative regulation of a liberal democratic regime's relation with the so-called decent peoples.

Rethinking the concept of peoples and the toleration of decent peoples

Before commenting on this issue, I want, in passing, to express my misgiving in relation to Rawls' theoretical resolution of recognizing the peoples as the central agents of the international domain and the primary subjects of international law. This particular position issues from a further development of the realistic, preoccupied with the ideal of stability and legitimacy, perspective adopted in Political Liberalism and so far discussed in this paper. More precisely, the guiding framework prescribing the embrace of an uncontroversial political conception of international justice likely to gain global acceptance compels the Rawlsian account to be less critical than it is required in its confrontation with the current structure of the international stage of affairs. By assigning to the peoples, as the collective political entities in their representation by their governments, the role of being the fundamental legal subjects of international justice, no significant departure is made from the current state-determined predicament of the international arena.

Rawls appeals to morality as the distinguishing mark between peoples and states. The peoples are characterized by moral sentiments and peaceful dispositions towards other peoples, whereas the states can't help making usage of their unshaken sovereignty to infringe on the liberty of other states for purposes rooted in self-interest. In one word, peoples are conceived as more keen to be reasonable and make justice their highest-order regulative interest, whereas the agency of states is monopolized by the imperatives of the deliberative rationality.

Admittedly, our historical experience offers an unfortunate vindication of the Rawlsian misgivings about the particular traditional sovereign states and their capacity to observe the norms of international justice and stability. However, it seems to me that the substitution of states with peoples, i.e., with an idealized version of states, makes little difference as regards the promotion of international justice and stability. Aside from the fact that the moral predisposition of peoples is anything but unquestionable (especially if one is reminded of the plethora of the unjust and brutal governments often supported or tolerated by their peoples), the moral disposition possesses no legal certification and authority in the domain of the international relations and its invocation is probably a mere wishful thinking. The appeal to the standpoint of morality in essence signifies that there is actually no objective guarantee that the peoples and their political representatives will ever develop other-regarding moral sensibilities, or that they will sincerely endorse principles of international law and act upon them.

In addition, unless the concern of realistic practicability is so tuned up as to shake the unconditioned rationality of normative philosophical theory, the states in their immediate particularity, even in their idealized version of peoples, do not meet the theoretical criteria for embodying the legitimate referents of the international political authority. On the one hand, the validation of their political status on the basis of common sympathy and shared cultural bonds among their members is unpromising, so long as those features are contingent upon random historical specificities that cannot be reasonably accounted for as factors of political relevance, let alone political legitimacy.

The point of view of any group of persons distinguished by certain subjective feelings for their national membership and by collective selfsatisfaction for their cultural achievements is hopelessly particularistic and impertinent to the universal rationality of political normativity. National and cultural affiliations and differentiations may be well appreciated as major players in a global civil society, but not in a global political society.

On the other hand, if this contingency is surmounted by placing emphasis, not on the cultural particularities, but on the political dimension of peoples, irrespective of their national, territorial and other random affiliations, then the universalizable rational nature of political normativity runs, again, counter to the recognition of any political authority to separate states, or peoples. A political constitution that frames principles of justice addressable to all rational beings is not reducible to a political rule dispersed, by virtue of cultural or national considerations, into a variety of discrete territories of sovereign political authority, even if this right to sovereignty is subjected to qualifications in a well-ordered international society, according to Rawls' prescription. Catherine Audard is of like mind stating that «letting peoples have a moral status and adding nationalism to the equation create a situation when one set of moral values is pitched against another, where individuals have hardly any claim against their governments in the name of national solidarity. Is that the best way to deal with moral issues such as the defense of vulnerable individuals, ethnic or religious minorities and dissidents in nonliberal countries, or with poverty and powerlessness in developing countries?». See Audard C. John Rawls. Acumen Publishing Limited, 2007. P.258. In short, the voluntary cultural and national associations may well comprise subjects of legal concern within the horizon of the international civil society, whereas the political rule must be addressed to rational persons, no matter of their natural features or their cultural, national and territorial affiliations. The shared by Rawls Kantian suspicion that a global political state is actually impracticable and susceptible to degenerating into despotism is reasonable in pragmatic terms but unappealing for a rational reconstruction of the conditions of just international interaction.

We have seen before that in the Rawlsian account the international world is divided in five types of peoples: liberal democratic peoples, decent peoples, outlaw states, societies burdened with unfavorable conditions and regimes politically organized as benevolent absolutisms. This division does not purport to provide a point by point illustration of the actual global political geography, but it is rather operative in an ideotypical fashion, on the basis of some certain criteria that measure the degree of a society's well-orderedness. On that account, the attribute of well-orderedness is accorded to liberal democratic and to decent peoples. The respect for the equality and self-determination of these types of peoples, as well as their reciprocal toleration, is for Rawls out of question. By contrast, the other kind of societies, either due to the injustice of their institutions, their corrupted political life or, even more significantly, their disrespect for human rights, are not regarded as of an equal moral footing with the liberal and decent societies. For this matter, they are to be treated by liberal democratic peoples in a manner ranging from total intolerance to assistance for purposes of institutional reformation. However, since the degree of toleration owed to nonliberal societies is measured by the degree of their respect for a considerably curtailed list of pre-political human rights, many critics, in large part those of a cosmopolitan liberal theoretical orientation, maintain that the qualifications for international toleration posed by Rawls are very relaxed. For reasons built into their individualistic social ontology at the international level, they are reluctant to accept even the equal treatment of decent peoples, accusing Rawls for unnecessary conformism and conservatism at this point.

The thrust of their argument is that, for reasons of consistency, the criterion of reasonableness and well-orderedness at the domestic domain, namely, the compliance with a full set of political democratic rights and civil liberties, ought to be extended internationally. In that respect, the standard of global justice should not be compromised by the introduction of an alternative to the criterion of reasonableness, less demanding criterion of decency. In other words, the imperatives of international justice are of the supreme import to be restricted and suspended on the basis of the concern for international stability and in the name of the respect allegedly owed to the autonomous self-determination of societies that run afoul of the liberal democratic conception of justice, that is, decent peoples.

To weigh up the critical force of these objections, let me first describe the central structural features that define the political and social predicament of decent peoples, which are alternatively being referred to as decent hierarchical societies in the Rawlsian taxonomy of peoples. The central feature of such societies, which may be embodied in a variety of institutional arrangements, is their associationist form, that is, «the members of these societies are viewed in public life as members of different groups, and each group is represented in the legal system by a body in a decent consultation hierarchy».LoP P. 64. Defined in this way, it is clear that those societies are far from honoring the individualistic culture of the modern western world, as cosmopolitan liberals would like it. Their social structure is much more reminiscent of the medieval corporatism, or the Hegelian civil society, whose members are politically represented only on the grounds of their group-membership and not their immediate individuality. Therefore, the «one person one vote» model of current democratic political operation is here absent, and what is to be politically represented are the common interests of the social groups that persons necessarily belong to. This sort of political representation is considered by the members of decent societies to be more fruitful, since what is being granted political voice is a more rationally refined version of the individual interest.

The collectivist political orientation of the associationist type of societies can well be accommodated in the «Society of Peoples» envisioned by Rawls, on the condition that two criteria are met. First, a society structured in the way just described can qualify for decency if «it does not have aggressive aims, and it recognizes that it must gain its legitimate ends through diplomacy and trade and other ways of peace». Ibid. That is, despite the fact that these societies are socially pervaded and politically governed on the grounds of their peculiar religious (or else) comprehensive doctrines, aspiring also to a more extensive international influence of these doctrines, they do so without failing to respect the independence of other societies, their separate political orders and the social and political liberties they grant to their citizens. So the first criterion of decency is the peaceful international policy that is based on diplomatic means. The second criterion is more complex and is constructed by Rawls in a three-partite manner: first, although an associationist type of society is regulated by a «common good idea of justice» that could be harmful to the inalienable liberties of its members as private persons, it does secure «for all members of the people what have come to be called human rights». LoP. P. 65. We will soon see in detail what counts for human rights for Rawls in this context, which has given rise to a good deal of discontent on the part of Rawls' readers, and indeed the most sympathetic of them. Second, a decent people's system of law «must be such as to impose bona fide moral duties and obligations (distinct from human rights) on all persons within the people's territory». LoP. P. 65-66. This provision is drawn upon Philip Soper's A Theory of Law and prescribes a political society's recognition of and respect for the rational and responsible character of its members, so that the duties and obligations imposed on them are consonant with their common good idea of justice, and not seen as «mere commands imposed by force». Third, judges and other officials in a well-ordered decent regime must sincerely and not unreasonably believe that «the law is indeed guided by a common good idea of justice» LoP. P. 66., actualizing this belief through the public defense, in courts, of social injunctions justified by law.

...

Подобные документы

  • The principles of the international law and the international contracts are the component of legal system of the Russian Federation. The question of application of the norms of the international law and contracts in activity of the Constitutional Court.

    реферат [16,0 K], добавлен 07.01.2015

  • Concept of the constitutional justice in the postsoviet Russia. Execution of decisions of the Constitutional Court. Organizational structure of the constitutional justice. Institute of the constitutional justice in political-legal system of Russia.

    реферат [23,9 K], добавлен 10.02.2015

  • The Constitutional Court of the Russian Federation essentially promotes entailment in life of the principles of justice, democracy. Analyze the judicial practice of the Constitutional Court of Republic Adygea. The Republican interpretation of freedom.

    реферат [20,2 K], добавлен 14.02.2015

  • Globalization of the theory, ideology and practice of modern constitutionalism on the border of millennia. The development of the constitutional ideas and institutes. Analyze the model of the Ukrainian constitutionalism and its realization in practice.

    реферат [25,5 K], добавлен 07.01.2015

  • Three models of juvenile system. The modern system of juvenile justice in Britain and Russia. Juvenile court. Age of criminal responsibility. Prosecution, reprimands and final warnings. Arrest, bail and detention in custody. Trial in the Crown Court.

    курсовая работа [28,2 K], добавлен 06.03.2015

  • The article covers the issue of specific breaches of international law provisions owed to Ukraine by Russia. The article also examines problems in the application of international law by Russia. In the course of the Russian aggression against Ukraine.

    статья [42,0 K], добавлен 19.09.2017

  • The role of constitutional justice in strengthening constitutional legality. Protection of the constitutional rights, freedoms, formation of the specialized institute of judicial power. The removal of contradictions and blanks in the federal legislation.

    реферат [24,0 K], добавлен 14.02.2015

  • The concept and features of the state as a subject of international law. The sovereignty as the basis of the rights and duties of the state. Basic rights and obligations of the state. The international legal responsibility of states. Full list of rights.

    курсовая работа [30,1 K], добавлен 17.05.2016

  • The role of constitutional principles in the mechanism of constitutional and legal regulation. Features of transformation in the interpretation principles. Relativism in the system of law. Local fundamental justice in the mechanism of the state.

    реферат [24,7 K], добавлен 10.02.2015

  • Creation history International Partnership for Human Rights. Projects aiming to advance the rights of vulnerable communities, such as women, children, migrants and minorities, who are subject to human rights abuses in different parts of the world.

    презентация [472,6 K], добавлен 04.10.2012

  • Formation of courts to protect constitutions. The nature of the Constitutional Court, its functions, structure, the order of formation and updating, the nature and the mechanism of execution of acts, a place and a role of the Constitutional Court.

    реферат [21,1 K], добавлен 14.02.2015

  • The international collective human rights' concept is still in process of development, and that we may say about many of international human rights. However, such a view is particularly true with regard to this group of rights.

    реферат [21,3 K], добавлен 10.06.2003

  • The Rule of Law is what some philosophers have called an essentially contestable concept. Grounds of agreement and disagreement. Four ideal-typical conceptions of the Rule of Law. Toward an integrated theory. An ideal that can never be realized perfectly.

    доклад [30,1 K], добавлен 16.06.2013

  • Constitutionalism as political and legal theory and practice of development of the constitutional democratic state and civil society. Principles of modern constitutional system of board. Role of society in the course of formation of municipal authority.

    реферат [18,5 K], добавлен 07.01.2015

  • History of antitrust law. The Department of Justice building in Washington, D.C. as home to the United States antitrust enforcers. Federal and state government, private suits. Several examples of antitrust law: AT&T, Alcoa, Kodak and Standard Oil.

    реферат [22,9 K], добавлен 26.06.2012

  • In world practice constitutional control is actually a develop institute with nearly bicentennial history. In this or that form it is presented and successfully functions in the majority of democratic states. Constitutionally legal liability in Russia.

    реферат [51,3 K], добавлен 10.02.2015

  • History of infantilism. Formation of the civil society and development of the lawful state. About the new constitution of Serbia. Introduction of obligatory examination for all state and municipal officials of knowledge of Constitution of the Russia.

    контрольная работа [20,1 K], добавлен 10.02.2015

  • Adoption of resolution about institution of the new Council on human rights. The role of the constitutional courts of the subjects of the RF is in rendering the influence upon adduction in correspondence of the legislation of the subjects of the RF.

    реферат [26,0 K], добавлен 14.02.2015

  • The first steps promoting creation of the judicial organs of the constitutional control in the subjects of the Russian Federation. Creation of the constitutional (charter) courts. System of organization of the power in the subjects of the Federation.

    реферат [17,4 K], добавлен 07.01.2015

  • Сritical comparison of Infrared analysis and Mass Spectrometry. Summary of the uses in forensic, the molecular structural mass spectral. The method provides better sensitivity in comparison. To conclude, both techniques are helpful in the forensic study.

    реферат [20,1 K], добавлен 21.12.2011

Работы в архивах красиво оформлены согласно требованиям ВУЗов и содержат рисунки, диаграммы, формулы и т.д.
PPT, PPTX и PDF-файлы представлены только в архивах.
Рекомендуем скачать работу.