Heraclitian dynamics in the Antigone and the fallacy of the right of the strongest

Study of the problem of limiting the right of the strongest in Greece. Highlighting the direct conflict between material power and moral power in the work of Sophocles "Antigone". Display of multiple and parallel dichotomies intertwined in the tragedy.

Ðóáðèêà Ëèòåðàòóðà
Âèä ñòàòüÿ
ßçûê àíãëèéñêèé
Äàòà äîáàâëåíèÿ 25.01.2023
Ðàçìåð ôàéëà 64,7 K

Îòïðàâèòü ñâîþ õîðîøóþ ðàáîòó â áàçó çíàíèé ïðîñòî. Èñïîëüçóéòå ôîðìó, ðàñïîëîæåííóþ íèæå

Ñòóäåíòû, àñïèðàíòû, ìîëîäûå ó÷åíûå, èñïîëüçóþùèå áàçó çíàíèé â ñâîåé ó÷åáå è ðàáîòå, áóäóò âàì î÷åíü áëàãîäàðíû.

Ðàçìåùåíî íà http://allbest.ru

Heraclitian dynamics in the Antigone and the fallacy of the right of the strongest

John D. Pappas John D. Pappas aGm Law Firm, Athens, Greece

Demetra Asimakopoulou Demetra Asimakopoulou National and Kapodistrian University of Athens, Athens, Greece

Abstract

The endless debates on Sophocles' Antigone reflect different analytical perspectives as to the multiple and concurrent dualities intertwined in the drama, like legality and legitimacy, lawfulness and morality, expediency and tradition, humans and the divine. Still, subjective perspectives notwithstanding, a conceptually and aesthetically prevalent duality in the Antigone pertains to the head-on conflict between (king Creon's) material power and (Antigone's) moral strength: Adult Creon's reasoning for enforcing his deadly kingly edict on adolescent Antigone is well founded with respect to the imperative need to maintain law and order in his dominion, as a necessary condition for reinstituting socio-political stability and ensuring the security and independence of his polis, especially in extreme conditions of civil warfare; nevertheless his aesthetically hubristic exertion of power leads the monarch's own family to self-destruction. In this mythological twist of fate, the Antigone brings to the fore artistically (and barely disputably) the limitations of the so-called right of the strongest, because the strongest is never strong enough to be always the master, unless he transforms strength into right, and obedience into duty.

Keywords: Sophocles' Antigone, hubris, nemesis, Peloponnesian War, illegitimate power, hegemony.

1. The spell of Ate in the Antigone1

In the ancient Greek world, hubris or ?âñéò was viewed as both insulting to the gods and violating the natural order of the cosmic universe: A hubristic action, which constitutes a substantial aberration from measure or ìÝôñïí (in classical works) or á?óéìá (in Homer's epics) is not in line with (or within the bounds of) the aberrant perpetrator's limitations or fate or destiny or (Homer's) á?óá.

As consequence, from an Heraclitian perspective2, hubris sets in motion the retributive forces of Nemesis or NÝìåóéò, the goddess that personifies justice and reinstitutes the balance of social and natural order by intervening violently to reinstitute the state of nature to a new equilibrium, because "through the future, both near and distant, as through the past, shall this law prevail: nothing that is vast comes to the life of mortals without ruin" (tot' ?ðåéôá êá? ô? ìÝëëïí êá? ô? ðñ?í ?ðáñêÝóåé íüìïò ?ä?, ï?ä?í ?ñðåé èíáô?í âéüô? ðÜìðïëý ã? ?êô?ò ?ôáò), as stated in the second stasimon of Sophocles' Antigone (l. 612-4).

To a subject of hubris, "evil at one time or another seems good" (to êáê?í äïêå?í ðïô? ?óèë?í) (l. 622) due to the intervention of goddess Ate or Atp, according to the classical dynamic scheme that involves the following intertwined concepts:

(1)

In general, "Ate instills confusion in the mind of every subject of hubristic behavior, and she thus personifies selfdestructive syndromes like defensive avoidance, overvigilance, reactivity and denial. These are ruinous states of mind that have led many economies, armies, states, and empires to disaster or even to collapse" [11, p. 83], i.e. to catastrophe or tisis (ôßóéò;), as consequence of the intervention of Nemesis (NÝìåóéò) after every trespassing or unsppaafa of a destined limit (l. 605-614):

Your power, great Zeus - what human overstepping can check it? Yours is power that neither Sleep, the all-ensnaring, nor the untiring months of the gods can defeat. Unaged through time, you rule by your power and dwell thereby in the brilliant splendor of Olympus. And through the future, both near and distant, as through the past, shall this law prevail: nothing that is vast comes to the life of mortals without ruin.

(TåÜí, Æå?, äýíáóéí ôßò ?íäñ?í ?ðåñâáóßá êáôÜó÷ïé, ô?í ï?è? ?ðíïò á?ñå? ðïè? ? ðÜíô? ?ãñåýùí, ï?ôå èå?í ?êìáôïé ì?íåò, ?ãÞñ? ä? ÷ñüí? äõíÜóôáò êáôÝ÷åéò ?ëýìðïõ ìáñìáñüåóóáí á?ãëáí. Tü ô? ?ðåéôá êá? ô? ìÝëëïí êá? ô? ðñ?í ?ðáñêÝóåé íüìïò ?ä?, ï?ä?í ?ñðåé èíáô?í âéüô? ðÜìðïëý ã? ?êô?ò ?ôáò)

In the second stasimon, this law is presented as absolute and universal, because when "a god leads a man to ruin then only for the briefest moment such man fares free of the grasp of Ate" (Atç" (èå?ò ?ãåé ðñ?ò ?ôáí: ðñÜóóåé ä? ?ëßãéóôïí ÷ñüíïí ?êô?ò ?ôáò) (l. 624-625).

2. Atean fallacy of strength

A historiographical example of the overwhelming spell of Ate on subjects of hubris is the failed attempt of Artabanus to avert the Persians from expanding their empire to Europe. Specifically, he gave the following strategic advice to Xerxes, as the latter was preparing to invade Greece:

Do you see how God does not allow the bigger animals to become insolently visible, as it is them that He strikes with his lightning rather than the smaller ones that never insult Him? Do you also see how He throws his bolts always against the tallest buildings and the tallest trees? Because God likes to draw back anything that stands out.

Likewise, even a mighty army may be discomfited by a small army, whenever God in His wrath exposes the former to fear [feelings of terror] or storm [natural disasters] through which they perish in a way unworthy of them. Because God allows no one to consider himself great, except Himself. (??ñ?ò ô? ?ðåñÝ÷ïíôá æ?á ?ò êåñáõíï? ? èå?ò ï?ä? ?? öáíôÜæåóèáé, ô? ä? óìéêñ? ï?äÝí ìéí êíßæåé: ?ñ?ò ä? ?ò ?ò ï?êÞìáôá ô? ìÝãéóôá á?å? êá? äÝíäñåá ô? ôïéá?ôá ?ðïóêÞðôåé ô? âÝëåá: öéëÝåé ã?ñ ? èå?ò ô? ?ðåñÝ÷ïíôá ðÜíôá êïëïýåéí. ï?ôù ä? êá? óôñáô?ò ðïëë?ò ?ð? ?ëßãïõ äéáöèåßñåôáé êáô? ôïéüíäå: ?ðåÜí óöé ? èå?ò öèïíÞóáò öüâïí ?ìâÜë? ? âñïíôÞí, äé? ?í ?öèÜñçóáí ?íáîßùò ?ùõô?í. O? ã?ñ ?? öñïíÝåéí ìÝãá ? èå?ò ?ëëïí ? ?ùõôüí (Herodotus, Histories 7.10e.))

Xerxes made the hubristic mistake of ignoring Artabanus' Heraclitean advice, because he was under the spell of Ate. The typical pairing of hubris and nemesis, that appears in many tragedies such as Sophocles' Oedipus Rex, Aeschylus' Agamemnon, and Euripides' Hippolytus, is almost always associated with the Homeric goddess Ate or equivalently with the Atean effect, i.e. a hubristic perpetrator's distorted perception of reality, in either mythological or historical time, as stated epigrammatically by the Chorus in the Antigone (l. 622). As a matter of fact, such Atean confusion in the mind of such perpetrator often maps to a chain of events in the ensuing human interaction or conflict, whose outcome is barely foreseeable. Indicatively, as to Sophocles' sense of nemesic unpredictability, the Parode of the Antigone includes a powerful description of the ferocious battle between the attacking (stronger) Argeians and the defending (weaker) Thebans (l. 125-140):

So fierce was the crash of battle swelling about his back, a match too hard to win for the rival of the dragon. For Zeus detests above all the boasts of a proud tongue. And when he saw them advancing in a swollen flood, arrogant their clanging gold, he dashed with brandished fire one who was already starting to shout victory when he had reached our ramparts. Staggered, he fell to the earth with a crash, torch in hand, a man possessed by the frenzy of the mad attack, who just now was raging against us with the blasts of his tempestuous hate. But his threats did not fare as he had hoped, and to the other enemies mighty Ares dispensed each their own dooms with hard blows, Ares, our mighty ally at the turning-point. (Tï?ïò ?ìö? í?ô? ?ôÜèç ðÜôáãïò ?ñåïò, ?íôéðÜë? äõó÷åßñùìá äñÜêïíôïò. Æå?ò ã?ñ ìåãÜëçò ãëþóóçò êüìðïõò ?ðåñå÷èáßñåé, êá? óöáò ?óéä?í ðïëë? ?åýìáôé ðñïóíéóóïìÝíïõò ÷ñõóï? êáíá÷?ò ?ðåñïðëßáéò, ðáëô? ?éðôå? ðõñ? âáëâßäùí ?ð? ?êñùí ?äç íßêçí ?ñì?íô? ?ëáëÜîáé. ?íôéôýð? ä? ?ð? ã? ðÝóå ôáíôáëùèå?ò ðõñöüñïò, ?ò ôüôå ìáéíïìÝí? î?í ?ñì? âáê÷åýùí ?ðÝðíåé ?éðá?ò ?÷èßóôùí ?íÝìùí. å?÷å ä? ?ëë? ô? ìÝí, ?ëëá ä? ?ð? ?ëëïéò ?ðåíþìá óôõöåëßæùí ìÝãáò ?ñçò äåîéüóåéñïò). In lines 106-121 Sophocles gives a poetic description of the siege of Thebes by the Argeian army, which seemed to be so strong or even invincible - as it "flew, like a screaming eagle, over into the Theban land' (?îÝá êëÜæùí ?åô?ò å?ò ã?í ?ò ?ðåñÝðôá) "in full armor' (ðáíóáãß?) "with a mass of weapons and crested helmets ... with spears thirsting for blood' (ðïëë?í ìåè? ?ðëùí îýí è? ?ððïêüìïéò êïñýèåóóéí... öïíþóáéóéí ëüã÷áéò) - that initially caused feelings of awe and terror to besieged Thebans. Still, from an analytical perspective of deterministic causality, (primarily) the bravery of the defenders, who were fighting for their freedom and the independence of their polis, in combination with (secondarily) the unforeseen dynamic of the battle, turned the battle against the (stronger) attackers, whose "threats did not fare as they had hoped", because to those (stronger) enemy forces "mighty Ares dispensed each their own dooms with hard blows" (å?÷å ä? ?ëë? ô? ìÝí, ?ëëá ä? ?ð? ?ëëïéò ?ðåíþìá óôõöåëßæùí ìÝãáò ?ñçò)) (l. 138-9) at the most critical moment, "the turning-point'3 or the critical point of the battle (l. 140) [4].

When the relatively stronger Argeians embarked on their military campaign, they were hubristically overconfident as to their future victory against the Thebans. Their overconfidence was Atëan because it was one-dimensional: The Argeians perceived their quantitative supremacy, in men and armor, as sufficient for ensuring their victory. They failed to see their moral inferiority vis-à-vis their adversary: They could not duly take into consideration the fact they were led in that war by a traitor, the Theban prince Polynices (Ðïëõíåßêçò), Antigone's brother. Consequently, the attacking Argeians failed to understand in time, before the battle, that the (materially weaker) Thebans were cornered to a moral dilemma between two ominous options: Either surrender and be ruled by a traitor - to the infamy of their polis and to the intergenerational shame of themselves - or fight to the end to defend their polis and their personal dignity. The Thebans opted for the second alternative. They thus made up for their deficiency in material strength by their supremacy in moral standing and thus in fighting morale. Consequently, the defending (weaker) Thebans won and the attacking (stronger) Argeians lost the battle, as frequently happens in human history.

This Sophoclean theme, i.e. victory of the materially weaker but morally stronger adversary, is in line with the collective memory of the Athenians and all Greeks in the Classical era, in the aftermath of the Persian invasion of mainland Greece in 492-479 BC, when two opposite value systems collided for the first time in history - the materialistic value system of Asia and the idealistic value system of pre- classical Greece, the former aiming at power, the latter at virtue. That conflict of values was outlined eloquently by Tigranes, son of Artabanus and Persian general in front of Mardonius, chief general of Xerxis, the hegemon of the Persian Empire at the time (480 BC):

Good heavens, Mardonius, what kind of men are these that you have pitted us against? It is not for material gain they contend but for virtue! (ðáðá? Ìáñäüíéå, êïßïõò ?ð? ?íäñáò ?ãáãåò ìá÷çóïìÝíïõò ?ìÝáò, ï? ï? ðåñ? ÷ñçìÜôùí ô?í ?ã?íá ðïéo?íôáé ?ëë? ðåñ? ?ñåô?ò (Herodotus, Histories, 8.26c)

Likewise, a conflict between two deviating value systems, i.e. between legality (enacted human law) and morality (perceived universal or divine law), takes center stage in the Antigone. Adult Creon is the seemingly powerful co-protagonist, the new victorious king of Thebes, whose first day of reign was gloriously marked by the great victory of his polis against the Argeian aggressors, right after the fratricidal elimination of Eteocles and Polynices, Antigone's brothers and contenders of the throne, who killed each other in the battle. On the contrary, Antigone is the seemingly powerless co-protagonist: She is adolescent and sister of an infamous traitor (Polynices). Moreover, as female, she is looked down on by Creon, as he explicitly states in his kingly and fatherly advice to prince Haemon (l. 677-680):

We must defend those who respect order, and in no way can we let a woman defeat us. It is better to fall from power, if it is fated, by a man's hand, than that we be called weaker than women. (?ìõíôÝ? ?óô? ôï?ò êïóìïõìÝíïéò, êï?ôïé ãõíáéê?ò ï?äáì?ò ?óóçôÝá. êñå?óóïí ãÜñ, å?ðåñ äå?, ðñ?ò ?íäñ?ò ?êðåóå?í, êï?ê ?í ãõíáéê?í ?óóïíåò êáëïßìåè? ?í). As wartime king, Creon is reasonably concerned primarily with political stability that may be effected by the enforcement of relative human law (i.e. by the application of the principle of legality at a certain point in spacetime) especially in the critical period right after the end of a ferocious civil war. Antigone though is equally reasonably concerned with intertemporal (eternal) divine will or absolute moral law (perceivably applicable to all humanity in all time), both in wartime and peacetime4.

The common denominator of the seemingly stronger protagonists in those dramas, mythological or historical, like the Argeian aggressors in mythological time, the Persian invaders in historical time and king Creon in the Antigone, is the Atean (narrow-minded) fallacy of strength, i.e. a perceived certainty (overconfidence) that the outcome of a conflict will necessarily favor the materially (quantitatively) strongest - although relative material strength in and by itself is neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition of victory in wartime or prevalence in peacetime.

3. From reasoning to aesthetics

The fallacy of strength notwithstanding, the argumentation of Creon (socio-political order and independence of his polis) is as rationally valid as that of Antigone (natural order and reverence to the divine). Both those arguments (l. 450-525) are isosthenic, i.e. equally valid (rational) in Epicurean terms, and therefore neither can be used as a sole criterion in and by itself for leading the audience to a conclusive and final (undisputable) judgment as to the two protagonists, i.e. as to who was the one that deviated hubristically away from measure (psipov) under those extreme conditions in wartime5. Still, the Sophoclean dual-protagonist structure of the Antigone, where one protagonist is adult male (Creon) and the other is adolescent female (Antigone), evokes the dramatic scenography of the conflict: Adult Creon and the elders of the Chorus, standing for all (adult male) citizens of Thebes, collude in entombing alive an adolescent female. Such horrible death is per se not merely unnatural (i.e. uncommon to other species on earth) but also aesthetically surreal. Moreover when the perpetrators are a group of adult males against an adolescent female, such entombing is obviously a sickening act of almost unimaginable or mythological perversion - a felony in the contemporary legal order the world over - as the Chorus implies in the fourth stasimon (l. 944-987). In Antigone's terminal mourning (Kommos or Êïììüò;), Sophocles highlights the aesthetics of the drama, by explicitly presenting Antigone, in her own words, as an adolescent "unwept, unfriended, without marriage-song' ((?êëáõôïò, ?öéëïò, ?íõìÝíáéïò;) (l. 876) doomed to meet her destiny all alone in her "tomb" (ôýìâïò), which she desperately and symbolically perceives as a distorted "bridal-chambef' (íõìöå?ïí) (l. 891). All alone, she speaks in awe and despair (In Antigone's Kommos, she is speaking to her tomb addressing it as her "bridal chamber'" (l. 891892): "Oh tomb! Oh bridal-chamber! Oh deep-dug eternal prison... " (? ôýìâïò, ? íõìöå?ïí, ? êáôáóêáö?ò ï?êçóéò ?åßöñïõñïò...). Sophocles has Antigone repeat that exclamation emphatically, three times on the same line, for a reason: to convey to the audience her awe and ultimate desperation as she turns to speak to her grave, just a few moments before she is led to the eternal darkness of her tomb and her horrible death. Such awe is conveyed adequately when that long- vowel exclamation (w) is pronounced with Hellenistic pronunciation, i.e. as "ooo" in high pitch, where every "o" is pronounced as in "volative" [1, p. 17, 20]: video clip of Antigone's Kommos in Ancient Greek at 1:30 with English subtitles here, with Ancient-Greek subtitles here].) to her tomb, and through the tomb to her dead brother, because nobody else in her polis wants to listen to her anymore. In the aesthetic context of entombing an adolescent female alive, Sophocles, defines king Creon's transgression (hubris) explicitly in the Antigone through seer Tiresias6, who characterizes Creon as "violator" of the divine will or (universal) moral law: "In the dead you have no part, nor do the gods above, but in this you do them violence" (?í ï?ôå óï? ìÝôåóôéí ï?ôå ôï?ò ?íù èåï?óéí, ?ëë? ?ê óï? âéÜæïíôáé ôÜäå) (l. 1072-1073). Sophocles' emphasis on such scenographical aesthetics of the tragedy paves the way to a partial resolution to endlessly irresolvable debates as to who of the two protagonists is "right". More specifically, in light of the "indeterminacy in the concept of measure" [11, p. 94], Sophocles offers his audience a complementary and enlightening criterion for subjective judgment as to the two protagonists: the aesthetics of the drama. Because measure and beauty are intertwined concepts (as manifested in the architecture of the Parthenon) while hubris and ugliness are also intertwined (as in the concentration camps of the Holocaust).

A basic problem in this respect, as far as the audience is concerned, is that not all humans are capable of aesthetically appreciating, or even seeing, (measured) beauty and its difference from (hubristic) ugliness in all situations and under all circumstances:

It is the human balance in which strength has reason to give way to weakness, and weakness has resources to find strength.

It is the human mean that can live only within a community. The best human life is a topic that demands philosophic reflection, but such reflection would not be possible if one could not, in the first place, simply see its form [13, p. 22]7.

In fact, the form of measure is not always visible to all humans all the time, for an evolutionary reason: The divine apportions natural boundaries to innately hybrid humans, i.e. to finite entities in an infinite evolutionary environment of continuous change per Heraclitus8. As such, humans are all potentially aberrant from measure, as reflected by the duality of the divine and the human perspectives in the Antigone, which tend to diverge rather than converge:

Nature and man have their boundaries apportioned to them. But the finite beings are unable to stay within these boundaries. They can only exist if they continue to partake of the power which has engendered them, if they keep sharing in the deinotes which has brought them into existence. But then power is doubled: on the one hand it is divine, apportioning power, on the other hand it manifests itself in finite entities. It is this duality that engenders the tragic conflict. The power concentrated in finite entities prevents them from accepting the boundaries set them. They are 'hybrid'. From the perspective of the entities themselves, they have to stay within their boundaries, but they have to transcend them as well. It is both necessary and impossible to avoid transgression. Because entities need strength in order to exist, they are unable to distinguish between the exercise of power inside and that outside their limits. . . In the Antigone the cosmic order is revealed in its duality. It is part of this order that finite beings transgress their limits and are destroyed. right greece antigone tragedy

Divine order is also disorder" [10, p. 203]. By nature, it is difficult for humans to see the form of measure and thus reach self-awareness as to their own personal limitations and predestined boundaries; but even if they do, it is still difficult for them as mortals to remain conscientiously within such boundaries. Consequently, the aesthetics of the drama might be conducive to the resolution of some but not all of the endless debates on the Antigone, as to the basic dualities of the plot, like legality and legitimacy, lawfulness and morality, locality and universality, order and change, society and family, individuality and personality, expediency and tradition, humans and the divine, as well as a gender gap and a generation gap, that are all quite apparent in the Antigone.

4. The fallacy of the right of the strongest

Sophocles wrote the Antigone probably in 438 B.C. [6, p. 35-50], just 7 years before the Peloponnesian War broke out, which was hubristically waged for nearly three decades (431-404 BC) to the infamy of Periclean Athens and to the self-destruction of classical Athens. The fatal fate of both the house of the Labdacids - the royal dynasty whose last male descendants were Eteocles and Polynices - and king Creon's family (l. 593) in the Antigone was to a certain degree similar to that of Athens. With a clairvoyant poet's foresight, Sophocles pefigures the catastrophic (nemesic) effects of the Athenians' imperial folly symbolically and prophetically9. In the Classical era, the Athenians set out to expand their victorious polis of moral virtue (?ñåôÞ) to an empire of "vast' (ðÜìðïëý) power (l. 614), in hubristic (distorted and imitative) application of the hegemonic paradigm of the defeated Persian Empire. From an aesthetic perspective, the Sophoclean dual-protagonist structure of the Antigone might reflect a specific political symbolism: Metaphorically, adult Creon might be viewed as standing for the hegemonists (politically "mature") of Periclean Athens, while adolescent Antigone as standing for the early unspoiled spirit of idealists (politically "adolescent") of pre-classical Athens a few decades earlier. Indicatively, Sophocles' implicit reference to the fragile and fateful (short-lived) Athenian Alliance - "where all the cities are stirred up in hostility (?÷èñá? ä? ð?óáé óõíôáñÜóóïíôáé ðüëåéò?) (l. 1080) - alludes to the enmity of most Greek poleis against the imperial transgressions of hegemonic Athens. That allusion, however metaphorical or indirect, was rather bold politically, given that Pericles himself might be sitting literally by Sophocles' side amidst the audience in performances of the Antigone at the time. Indeed, the allusion is stressed by seer Tiresias' harsh or even contemptuous words against king Creon, as if Sophocles were addressing through Tiresias the Athenians or even Pericles himself: "There, now, are arrows for your heart... launched at you, archer-like ... They fly true - you cannot run from their burning sting' (ôïéá?ôÜ óïõ, ëõðå?ò ãÜñ, ?óôå ôïîüôçò ?ö?êá èõì?, êáñäßáò ôïîåýìáôá âÝâáéá, ô?í ó? èÜëðïò ï?÷ ?ðåêäñáìå?) (l. 1084-1086). At the time, it might have been obvious to Sophocles, as to the other Great Tragedians, that Greece had been going hubristically far beyond measure as soon as the independent city-states formed confederations and expansionary alliances that battled one another over a hubristically unrealistic prize, i.e. politico-economic dominance all over Greece and even beyond, in emulation of the Asian paradigm. Indeed, the Athenian hubris of disproportionate imperialistic expansion, entangled them to a vicious circle of self-destruction in the Peloponnesian War, wherein their glorious polis lost its moral and cultural stature by committing crimes against humanity, like the Athenian Massacre of Melos (416 BC) or even the execution of Socrates (399 BC). In specific, the Athenians considered the Massacre of Melos as a reasonably justifiable act of strategic pragmatism. They stated epigrammatically (and quite unscrupulously) to the Melians the so-called right of the strongest (Thucydides, Histories 5.89): "right, as the world perceives it, is only in question between equals in power, while the strong do what they can and the weak suffer what they must"((äßêáéá ì?í ?í ô? ?íèñùðåß? ëüã? ?ð? ô?ò ?óçò ?íÜãêçò êñßíåôáé, äõíáô? ä? ï? ðñïý÷ïíôåò ðñÜóóïõóé êá? ï? ?óèåíå?ò îõã÷ùñï?óéí). The implied meaning of this excerpt may be duly comprehended only if it is analyzed within the wider context of Histories: A widespread fallacy is that through this excerpt Thucydides states his own point of view that the right of the strongest is a fundamental determinant in human interaction and international relations. This fallacy though overlooks two basic facts: (a) the hegemonist Athenians, not Thucydides the historian, proclaimed the right of the strongest, and (b) the entire masterpiece of Histories is virtually a thesis about the catastrophic repercussions of that perverted hegemonic (hubristic) concept10 upon their own glorious polis, their shortlived Athenian Alliance, and ultimately all Classical Greece.

Obviously, the novice imperialist Athenians had become incapable of viewing their hubristic crime as an act of genocidal barbarism, i.e. as a horrendous crime that would bring upon them the retribution of cosmic Justice (Nemesis) in the form of their devastating defeat in the Peloponnesian War and ultimately the downfall of their polis as an independent city-state thereafter, as prescribed by Heraclitus, as prefigured by Sophocles in the Antigone, and as described analytically by Thucydides in his Histories. At the time, under the spell of Ate, the Athenians, perceived those crimes as rationally justifiable on the grounds of (perceived) political expediency, i.e. projection of imperialist power through the annihilation of Melos. Soon thereafter, they committed another crime, the execution of Socrates, to their eternal infamy, on the grounds of intended sociopolitical cohesion of their polis, which assumedly was threatened by Socrates' criticism of both democrats and oligarchs in the aftermath of the Peloponnesian War [5, p. 92-94] - the latter grounds being similar to those of king Creon's reasoning in the Antigone, i.e. the perceived imperative need for applying the principle of legality absolutely (akin to Roman dura lex, sed lex) for ensuring social cohesion and political stability. Like the mythological Argeians and king Creon in the Antigone, the historical Athenians had become unable to see the ugliness of their crimes and sense or perceive their loss of proportion11. As nemesic consequence of their hubristic aberration from measure (ìÝôñïí), their polis lost its independence just a few decades thereafter once and for all, while the Athenians themselves - like the Theban royal house of the Labdacids as well as king Creon's own family12 in the Antigone - were genetically annihilated in the following centuries13. At least, no Athenian in the Classical era could blame Sophocles that he did not forewarn them, albeit to no effect, as to the unsustainability of the Athenian Alliance and the long-term (YHP9 or in old age) repercussions of their hubristic hegemonic transgressions (l. 1347-1352):

"Thinking prudently14 is a prime precondition of prosperity, and our dealings with the gods must be in no way unholy, not even once. And the great words, having repaid arrogant men with great blows, have taught them how to think prudently in their old age".

(ðïëë? ô? öñïíå?í å?äáéìïíßáò ðñ?ôïí ?ðÜñ÷åé. ÷ñ? ä? ôÜ ã? å?ò èåï?ò ìçä?í ?óåðôå?í. ìåãÜëïé ä? ëüãïé ìåãÜëáò ðëçã?ò ô?í ?ðåñáý÷ùí ?ðïôßóáíôåò ãÞñ? ô? öñïíå?í ?äßäáîáí). In the above phrase ìçä?í ?óåðôå?í ("in no way unholy, not even once"), ìçä?í is translated in English in an augmented 6- word descriptive double phrase ("in no way... not even once") to point out Sophocles' zero tolerance of irreverence to the divine or equivalently of violations of the moral law, given that ìçä?í - etym. ìçä? (meaning "not even") + ?í (meaning "one") - is neutral-gender form of the masculine-gender word pqScfg ("not even one"). In general, the Sophoclean zero tolerance of irreverence or injustice is in line with the Aristotelean zero tolerance of any act of injustice15.

Conclusion

In conclusion though, both mythological king Creon and the historical Athenians were mentally carried away by their past triumphs and failed to pay due attention to legitimacy, adherence to morality, and reverence to divine order (universal norms) in their own present time. They consequently failed to avoid disasters in their near or foreseeable future and ultimately Ate led them all to their pathetic self-destruction, effected by invincible Nemesis. Because from a Sophoclean perspective, implied in the Antigone, the triptych justice, morality and reverence - the latter also known as the Roman virtue pietas - is a necessary condition of sustainability, i.e. these virtues in combination may enable individuals, states or Great Powers to think prudently (9pov£Tv) and thus ensure their prosperity (cuSaipovfa).

Acknowledgement: The authors are indebted to Svitlana Grytsenko, Olesia Lazer-Pankiv, Igor Korolyov, Olena Materynska of the Bulletin of Taras Shevchenko National University of Kyiv. Literary Studies. Linguistics. Folklore Studies, for their meticulous bibliographical and overall editing and layout of the article, as well as for the accurate translation of the title and abstract in Ukrainian.

Notes

1 In this monograph, all original text of the Antigone, in Ancient Greek, has been copied from F. Starr's [14] first volume of two-volume Sophocles, as it appears in digital form in the Perseus Digital Library of Tufts University. All Greek words herein are hyperlinked to the Lid- dell-Scott Greek-English online lexicon in that library.

2 The concept hubris or hybris (?âñéò) was introduced into modern academic literature by Friedrich Nietzsche as of 1873 by his incomplete treatise Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks.

He explicitly connects this classical concept with Heraclitus [9, p. 61]: "That dangerous word hybris is indeed the touchstone for every Heraclitan. Here he must show whether he has understood or failed to recognize his master'. In English, the term hubris means excessive pride, insolent self-confidence, or haughtiness.

3 The descriptive translation of " äåîéüóåéñïò" - which means literally the "leading" horse, the first one in the right row (5º^³à ñòàðà) of the horses of a chariot - into "our mighty ally at the turning-point' enables the English-speaking reader to understand that Ares, the god of war, did not wage the battle by himself, all alone, for the Thebans, but instead the Theban army fought bravely and won the war in "alliance" with "mighty" Ares, who stands for the unpredictable dynamic of the battle.

4 Antigone's adherence to the norms of intertemporal (eternal) divine will or absolute moral law is stated by herself conscientiously and knowledgeably in her heated apologetic conversation with king Creon (l. 450-459):

Since it was not Zeus that published me that edict, and since not of that kind are the laws which Justice who dwells with the gods below established among men. Nor did I think that your decrees were of such force, that a mortal could override the unwritten and unfailing statutes given us by the gods. For their life is not of today or yesterday, but for all time, and no man knows when they were first put forth. Not for fear of any man's pride was I about to owe a penalty to the gods for breaking these.

(ï? ãÜñ ôß ìïé Æå?ò ?í ? êçñýîáò ôÜäå, ï?ä? ? îýíïéêïò ô?í êÜôù èå?í Äßêç ôïéïýóä? ?í ?íèñþðïéóéí ?ñéóåí íüìïõò. ï?ä? óèÝíåéí ôïóï?ôïí ?üìçí ô? ó? êçñýãìáè?, ?óô? ?ãñáðôá ê?óöáë? èå?í íüìéìá äýíáóèáé èíçô?í ?íè? ?ðåñäñáìå?í. ï? ãÜñ ôé í?í ãå ê?÷èÝò, ?ëë? ?åß ðïôå æ? ôá?ôá, êï?äå?ò ï?äåí ?î ?ôïõ 'öÜíç. ôïýôùí ?ã? ï?ê ?ìåëëïí, ?íäñ?ò ï?äåí?ò öñüíçìá äåßóáó?, ?í èåï?óé ô?í äßêçí äþóåéí).

5 From a certain perspective, it might seem that Creon is a rightful defender of the law and social order, while Antigone is a (hubristic) violator of the law or even a (traitorous) rebel in wartime [7, p. 4-15; 2, p. 504-516].

6 Seer Tiresias was an omnipresent transgenerational figure in mythological Thebes: His long life spanned seven generations, starting from Cadmus, founder of the royal house of Thebes. As a wise clairvoyant adhering to common sense and natural order, he mediates between the future and the past, the living and the dead, this world and the underworld, humans and the gods, logic and intuition, the earthly and the transcendental, the seeing and the blind, male and female. In his young age, he became a priestess of Hera, when that goddess transformed him to a woman for seven years. In sum, Tiresias is an Apollonian figure that wanders around mythological Thebes and evolves amidst an intertemporal Dionysiac processus of unpredictable chain of events in human affairs.

7 Obviously - notwithstanding the issue of whether most humans really have a sense of measure so that they can "simply see its form" - that important (aesthetical) aspect of the conflict between the two protagonists (an adult male versus an adolescent female) may be lost aesthetically on stage to a considerable degree in performances where Antigone is impersonated by an adult actor.

8 According to Plato, "Heraclitus says, somewhere, that 'all things move and nothing remains still,' and he likens the universe to the current of a river, saying that 'you cannot step twice into the same river "

(ëÝãåé ðïõ ?ñÜêëåéôïò ?ôé 'ðÜíôá ÷ùñå? êá? ï?ä?í ìÝíåé,' êá? ðïôáìï? ?ï? ?ðåéêÜæùí ô? ?íôá ëÝãåé ?ò 'ä?ò ?ò ô?í á?ô?í ðïôáì?í ï?ê ?í ?ìâáßçò') (Plato, Cratylus 402a).

9 Antigone's monologue in Kommos has some common characteristics with the Passions of Christ: For example, her words of desperation "Why should I look to the gods anymore?" ((ôß ÷ñÞ ìå ô?í äýóôçíïí ?ò èåï?ò ?ôé âëÝðåéí;) (l. 922) is akin to Jesus' words on the Cross "My God, my God, why have you forsaken me?" (ÈåÝ ìïõ èåÝ ìïõ, ?íá ôß ìå ?ãêáôÝëéðåò;)) (Matthew 27.46); her statement "by my reverence I have earned a name for irreverence" (Tpv áèñòñòÅðÅà ÅèñòÅðîéñòà £êòã|ñòàðô/) (l. 924) could be an epigrammatic epitome of the Holy Passions (ô?í äõóóÝâåéáí å?óåâï?óá ?êôçóÜìçí); and so on.

Still, Antigone is barely forgiving to all those guilty of her horrible death. Her last words "I could wish for them no greater evils than they inflict unjustly on me" (ì? ðëåßù êáê? ðÜèïéåí ? êá? äñ?óéí ?êäßêùò ?ìÝ) (l. 929) fall short the (transcendental) saying of Jesus' "Father, forgive them, for they don't know what they are doing" (?öåò á?ôï?ò, ï? ã?ñ ï?äáóéí ôß ðïéï?óéí) (Luke 23.34). Antigone's wish connotes the fundamental judicial principle of proportional reciprocity (not Jesus' unconditional forgiveness) that was later propounded and elaborated by Aristotle. More specifically, Antigone's last words barely reflect the principle of lex talionis (legal equivalence, as in "equivalent retaliation"), which traces its origins to the Babylonian code (enacted in 1772 BC by Hammurabi, the sixth king of Babylon) and to the Biblical scripture "an eye for an eye" or "|'ii ëïë |'ii" (Leviticus 24:20; Exodus 21:24; Deuteronomy 19:21): She does not wish those guilty of her death a punishment that would be as great as hers, but instead one that would be "no greater than" hers (pp ïËå³ø), alluding to proportional reciprocity, which takes into consideration extenuating circumstances, e.g. the fragile state of affairs in her polis right after the end of the civil war as well as the extinction of the royal name of her father ever since.

According to Aristotle, proportionate reciprocity with qualification that takes account of circumstances, is the sort of justice that safeguards social cohesion and the sustainability of the city-state (polis): "This sort of justice does hold men together: reciprocity in accordance with a proportion and not on the basis of precisely equal return. For it is by proportionate requital that the city-state holds together" (ÓõíÝ÷åé ô? ôïéï?ôïí äßêáéïí, ô? ?íôéðåðïíè?ò êáô? ?íáëïãßáí êá? ì? êáô? ?óüôçôá. Ô? ?íôéðïéå?í ã?ñ ?íÜëïãïí óõììÝíåé ? ðüëéò.) (Aristotle, Ethics 1132b: 33-35).

10 Twenty-two (22) centuries after Sophocles and Thucydides, Rousseau [12] characterized the Athenian concept of the right of the strongest as irrational "nonsense" and rejected it altogether explicitly in The Social Contract (book I, ch. III): The strongest is never strong enough to be always the master, unless he transforms strength into right, and obedience into duty . . . Force is a physical power, and I fail to see what moral effect it can have. To yield to force is an act of necessity, not of will - at the most, an act of prudence. In what sense can it be a duty?. .. If force creates right, the effect changes with the cause: every force that is greater than the first succeeds to its right.

As soon as it is possible to disobey with impunity, disobedience is legitimate; and, the strongest being always in the right, the only thing that matters is to act so as to become the strongest. But what kind of right is that which perishes when force fails? . . . Clearly, the word "right" adds nothing to force: in this connection, it means absolutely nothing...Let us then admit that force does not create right, and that we are obliged to obey only legitimate powers.

11 The classical concept of measure or sense of proportion, which is the implied thematic cornerstone of the Antigone, has geopolitical significance and applicability. For example, Franklin D. Roosevelt, 32nd President of the United States (1933-1945), attempted to avert the Greek Civil War (1944-1949) by sending, through Winston S. Churchill, then Prime Minister of the United Kingdom in wartime, a Presidential message (18 April 1944) to the political and military leaders of the warring Greek factions, in which he stated, albeit to no effect [3, p. 484-485]: "I hope that Greeks everywhere will set aside pettiness and regain their sense of proportion. Let every Greek think of their glorious past and show personal unselfishness which is so necessary now".

12 At the end of the drama, king Creon reaches self-awareness and rushes belatedly to Antigone's tomb to save her life, alas to no avail (l. 1204-1225): Upon his arrival in her tomb, he finds Antigone dead and nearly witnesses his son, prince Haemon, committing suicide by the side of his beloved Antigone, soon to be followed by Creon's wife, Queen Eurydice, who also committed suicide in despair over her son's death.

13 Indicatively, at the time of the destruction of the Parthenon (1687 AD), the ultimate symbol of the Athenian democracy, no descendant of ancient Athenians existed in their polis - which has been a historical and tragic city of great accomplishments, hubristic crimes and nemesic self-destruction.

14 In this stanza (l. 1347-1352), Sophocles lays stress on "to 9pov£fv" which means "thinking prudently". The Chorus members repeat it twice in the closing stanza of the Antigone (l. 1347, 1352) in gerund form: (article) to + (infinitive) öñïíå?í. Specifically, 9pov£w is the verbal form of öñüíçóéò, which means "prudence", as in the sentence "Strength combined with prudence is indeed an advantage, but without prudence it harms more than it helps its possessors". (?þìç ä? ìåô? ì?í öñïíÞóåùò ?öÝëçóåí, ?íåõ ä? ôáýôçò ðëåßù ôï?ò ?÷ïíôáò ?âëáøå ) (Isocrates, to Demonicus 1.6). Sophocles uses gerund (to öñïíå?í), instead of noun öñüíçóéò), in order to connote that wisdom (óïößá) is an attribute only of those who think prudently not merely sometimes but all the time, continuously.

According to the Classics, as implied above, thinking sometimes prudently might be taught through education as an (externally predefined) learning process, but wisdom (óïößá) is a mental state or personality attribute (?ñåô? or virtue) that could only be achieved through thinking all the time prudently, which is preconditioned on open-mindedness and self-discipline.

15 Aristotle's zero (ìçäÝí) tolerance of acts of injustice (?äéêå?óèáé) is epigrammatically stated as "to commit not even one act of injustice" or "?äéêå?óèáé ìçäÝí" (Aristotle, Politics 5.1315a: 34-35): "And whereas politically organized societies (poleis) consist of two classes, the people with no economic resources and those in control of such resources, it is most important for both to think they owe their safety to the government and to commit not even one act of injustice against each other" (?ðåß ä?á? ðüëåéò ?ê äýï óõíåóôÞêáóé ìïñßùí, ?ê ôå ô?í ?ðüñùí ?íèñþðùí êá? ô?í å?ðüñùí, ìÜëéóôá ì?í ?ìöïôÝñïõò ?ðïëáìâÜíåéí äå? ó?æåóèáé äé? ô?í ?ñ÷Þí, êá? ôï?ò ?ôÝñïõò ?ð? ô?í ?ôÝñùí ?äéêå?óèáé ìçäÝí

References

1. Asimakopoulou, Demetra (2017), Sophocles' Antigone: Hyperlinked compendium for ancient-drama immersion of English-speaking students in Ancient Greek - ABRIDGED version (published under the auspices of UNESCO and the Greek Ministry of Education and under license of Tufts University / the Perseus Digital Library) pp. 17, 20.

2. Charen, Hannes (2011). "The Purity of Her Crime - Hegel Reading Antigone", Monatshefte, 103.4: 504-516.

3. Churchill, Winston L. S. Sir (1951). The Second World War (New York), vol. 5 (Closing the Ring), Book II (Teheran to Rome), ch. XIII (The Greek Torment) 484-485.

4. Collins, Randall (2007). "Turning Points, Bottlenecks and the Fallacies of Counterfactual History", Sociological Forum, 22.3: 247-249.

5. Guthrie, William Keith Chambers (1969). A History of Greek Philosophy (Cambridge, UK) 3.2; 92-94.

6. Lewis, R. G. (1988), "An Alternative Date for Sophocles' Antigone", Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 29.1: 35-50.

7. Lines, Patricia M. (1999). "Antigone's Flaw", Humanitas, 12.1: 4-15.

8. Molyneux, John H. (1992). Simonides; A historical study (Wauconda, Illinois) 15o.

9. Nietzsche, Friedrich (1873). Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks, (Washington, D.C.: 1962) 61.

10. Oudemans, Th. C. W. and André P. M. H. Lardinois (1987). Tragic Ambiguity - Anthropology, Philosophy and Sophocles' Antigone (Netherlands) 159, 203.

11. Pappas, John D (2014). "The Concept of Measure and the Criterion of Sustainability", The St. John's Review, 56.1: 83, 94.

12. Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1762). Du Contrat Social; ou, Principes du Droit Politique (M.M. Rey: Geneva 1762) I.III, pp. 10-12; English trans. in: On The Social Contract & Discources (Dent: London 1913) book I, ch. III.

13. Sachs, Joe (2002). "Measure, Moderation, and the Mean", The St. John's Review, 46.2: 22.

14. Storr, Francis (1912). Sophocles (Heinemann: New York), vol. 1 (Oedipus the king; Oedipus at Colonus; Antigone).

Àíîòàö³ÿ

Ãåðàêë³ò³âñüêà äèíàì³êà â "Àíò³ãîí³" é îìàíëèâ³ñòü ïðàâà íàéñèëüí³øîãî

Äæîí Ä. Ïàïïàñ AGM Law Firm, Àô³íè, Ãðåö³ÿ

Äåìåòðà Àñèìàêîïóëó Àô³íñüêèé íàö³îíàëüíèé óí³âåðñèòåò ³ìåí³ Êàïîäèñòð³¿, Àô³íè, Ãðåö³ÿ

Íåñê³í÷åíí³ äåáàòè ïðî "Àíò³ãîíó" Ñîôîêëà â³äîáðàæàþòü ð³çí³ àíàë³òè÷í³ òî÷êè çîðó ùîäî ïåðåïëåòåíèõ ó äðàì³ ìíîæèííèõ ³ ïàðàëåëüíèõ äèõîòîì³é, ñåðåä ÿêèõ ëåãàëüí³ñòü ³ ëåã³òèìí³ñòü, çàêîíí³ñòü ³ ìîðàëü, äîö³ëüí³ñòü ³ òðàäèö³ÿ, ëþäñüêå ³ áîæåñòâåííå. ² âñå æ, íåçâàæàþ÷è íà ñóá'ºêòèâí³ òî÷êè çîðó, êîíöåïòóàëüíî òà åñòåòè÷íî äîì³íàíòíà äèõîòîì³ÿ â "Àíò³ãîí³" ñòîñóºòüñÿ ïðÿìîãî êîíôë³êòó ì³æ ìàòåð³àëüíîþ âëàäîþ (öàðÿ Êðåîíòà) ³ ìîðàëüíîþ ñèëîþ (Àíò³ãîíè). Ó öüîìó êîíòåêñò³ ì³ðêóâàííÿ äîðîñëîãî Êðåîíòà ùîäî âèêîíàííÿ ñâîãî öàðñüêîãî íàêàçó ïðî ñìåðòíèé âèðîê þí³é Àíò³ãîí³ º ö³ëêîì îá´ðóíòîâàíèìè. Íàñàìïåðåä éäåòüñÿ ïðî íàãàëüíó ïîòðåáó ï³äòðèìóâàòè ïðàâîïîðÿäîê ó ñâîºìó âîëîä³íí³ ÿê íåîáõ³äíó óìîâó â³äíîâëåííÿ ñîö³àëüíî-ïîë³òè÷íî¿ ñòàá³ëüíîñò³ òà çàáåçïå÷åííÿ áåçïåêè ³ íåçàëåæíîñò³ éîãî ïîë³ñó, îñîáëèâî â åêñòðåìàëüíèõ óìîâàõ ãðîìàäÿíñüêî¿ â³éíè. Âîäíî÷àñ åñòåòè÷íî ã³áðèñòè÷íèé ïðîÿâ âëàäè Êðåîíòà ïðèçâîäèòü âëàñíó ðîäèíó ïðàâèòåëÿ äî ñàìîçíèùåííÿ. Ó öüîìó ì³ôîëîã³÷íîìó ïîâîðîò³ äîë³ Àíò³ãîíà âïðàâíî (³ áåççàïåðå÷íî) âèñóâຠíà ïåðøèé ïëàí ïðîáëåìó îáìåæåííÿ òàê çâàíîãî ïðàâà íàéñèëüí³øîãî, àäæå íàéñèëüí³øèé í³êîëè íå áóâຠäîñòàòíüî ñèëüíèì, ùîá çàâæäè áóòè ãîñïîäàðåì, õ³áà ùî â³í ïåðåòâîðþº ñèëó íà ïðàâî, à ïîñëóõ - íà îáîâ'ÿçîê.

Êëþ÷îâ³ ñëîâà: "Àíò³ãîíà" Ñîôîêëà, ã³áðèñ (çàðîçóì³ë³ñòü), íåìåçèäà, Ïåëîïîííåñüêà â³éíà, íåëåã³òèìíà âëàäà, ãåãåìîí³ÿ.

Ðàçìåùåíî íà Allbest.ru

...

Ïîäîáíûå äîêóìåíòû

  • The study of biography and literary work of Jack London. A study of his artistic, political and social activities. Writing American adventure writer, informative, science-fiction stories and novels. The artistic method of the writer in the works.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [799,5 K], äîáàâëåí 10.05.2015

  • Modern development of tragedy, the main futures of the hero. A short biography and features a creative way of Arthur Miller, assessment of his literary achievements and heritage. Tragedy of Miller in "The crucible", features images of the main character.

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [32,3 K], äîáàâëåí 08.07.2016

  • The Globe Theatre. "Romeo and Juliet" - an optimistic tragedy. Staged in all kinds of theaters. "Othello" is a play about love and jealousy. "King Lear" is the story of a man who was so proud so egoistic that he could not understand a world around him.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [918,5 K], äîáàâëåí 25.03.2013

  • Shevchenko - Ukrainian poet, writer, artist, academician of the Imperial Academy of Arts. Biography: childhood and youth, military service in the Orenburg region, St. Petersburg period. National, religious, moral, and political motives in his works.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [1,5 M], äîáàâëåí 23.09.2014

  • Biographical information and the Shakespeare - English poet and playwright, the beginning of his literary activity, the first role in the theater. The richness of the creative heritage of the poet: plays, poems-sonnets, chronicle, tragedy and Comedy.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [902,2 K], äîáàâëåí 15.05.2015

  • Biography of William Somerset Maugham and Joseph Conrad is English playwrights, novelists and short story writers. The stages of their creative development, achievements. The moral sense in Joseph Conrad’s Lord Jim. Some problems in "Of Human Bondage".

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [52,7 K], äîáàâëåí 08.07.2016

  • Story about relationships of uncle Silas and his housekeeper. The main character of the story. Housekeeper as the minor character. Place of the conflicts in the story. The theme of the story. Stylistic devices in the text of the story, examples.

    àíàëèç êíèãè [5,2 K], äîáàâëåí 05.05.2012

  • The study of the tale by Antoine de Saint-Exupery "The Little Prince". The reflection in her true essence of beauty, the meaning of life. The salvation of mankind from the impending inevitable catastrophe as one of the themes in the works of the writer.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [3,3 M], äîáàâëåí 26.11.2014

  • Description of the life and work of American writers: Dreiser, Jack London, F. Fitzgerald, E. Hemingway, Mark Twain, O. Henry. Contents of the main works of the representatives of English literature: Agatha Christie, Galsworthy, Wells, Kipling, Bronte.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [687,6 K], äîáàâëåí 09.12.2014

  • Life and work of Irish writers of the late Victorian era, George Bernard Shaw. Consideration of the interpretation of the myth of the Greek playwright Ovid about the sculptor Pygmalion Cypriots against the backdrop of Smollett's novels and Ibsen.

    ðåôåðàò [22,2 K], äîáàâëåí 10.05.2011

  • Role of the writings of James Joyce in the world literature. Description the most widespread books by James Joyce: "Dubliners", "Ulysses". Young Irish artist Stephen Dedalus as hero of the novel. An Analysis interesting facts the work of James Joyce.

    ðåôåðàò [48,5 K], äîáàâëåí 10.04.2012

  • The biography of English writer Mary Evans. A study of the best pastoral novels in English literature of the nineteenth century. Writing a writer of popular novels, social-critical stories and poems. The success of well-known novels of George Eliot.

    ñòàòüÿ [9,0 K], äîáàâëåí 29.10.2015

  • Stephen King, a modern sci-fi, fantasy writer, assessment of its role in American literature. "Shawshank redemption": Film and Book analysis. Research of the content and subject matter of this work and its social significance, role in world literature.

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [29,2 K], äîáàâëåí 06.12.2014

  • Political power as one of the most important of its kind. The main types of political power. The functional analysis in the context of the theory of social action community. Means of political activity related to the significant material cost-us.

    ðåôåðàò [11,8 K], äîáàâëåí 10.05.2011

  • The Chernobyl disaster is a huge global problem of 21st century. Current status of Chernobyl NPP. The most suitable decision of solving problem of wastes is a reburial in the repository "Buryakovka". The process of the Arch assembling and sliding.

    ðåôåðàò [396,5 K], äîáàâëåí 19.04.2011

  • Understanding the science of constitutional law. Organization of state power and the main forms of activity of its bodies. The study of the constitutional foundations of the legal status of the citizen, local government. Research on municipal authorities.

    ðåôåðàò [15,3 K], äîáàâëåí 14.02.2015

  • The definition of conformism as passive acceptance and adaptation to standards of personal conduct, rules and regulations of the cult of absolute power. Study the phenomenon of group pressure. External and internal views of subordination to the group.

    ðåôåðàò [15,3 K], äîáàâëåí 14.05.2011

  • Placing the problem of human rights on foreground of modern realization. The political rights in of the Islamic Republic Iran. The background principles of vital activity of the system of judicial authorities. The executive branch of the power in Iran.

    ðåôåðàò [30,2 K], äîáàâëåí 14.02.2015

  • Power Point ïðîãðàììà äëÿ ñîçäàíèÿ ïðåçåíòàöèé, êîòîðûå íåîáõîäèìû âî ìíîãèõ ñôåðàõ ïðîôåññèîíàëüíîé äåÿòåëüíîñòè. Âîçìîæíîñòè è íàñòðîéêà ïðîãðàììû Power Point. Çàïóñê ïðîãðàììû, ìàñòåð àâòîñîäåðæàíèÿ. Ñïîñîá âûâîäà ïðåçåíòàöèè è øàáëîíû îôîðìëåíèÿ.

    ðåôåðàò [635,5 K], äîáàâëåí 13.09.2010

  • The Structure of Ukrainian Government. Rights and Duties of the Ukrainian Citizens. The Constitution of Ukraine. The state language. The Verkhovna Rada's main function is making laws. The Cabinet of Ministers is the highest body of the executive power.

    êîíòðîëüíàÿ ðàáîòà [15,3 K], äîáàâëåí 13.11.2010

Ðàáîòû â àðõèâàõ êðàñèâî îôîðìëåíû ñîãëàñíî òðåáîâàíèÿì ÂÓÇîâ è ñîäåðæàò ðèñóíêè, äèàãðàììû, ôîðìóëû è ò.ä.
PPT, PPTX è PDF-ôàéëû ïðåäñòàâëåíû òîëüêî â àðõèâàõ.
Ðåêîìåíäóåì ñêà÷àòü ðàáîòó.