The real as problem in Fichte’s doctrine of knowledge

How can the determinable be conceived of as itself determinate - the question of epistemology. Fichte’s inoculation of incomprehensibility in the system of transcendental philosophy - a noetic transcendence immanent in knowing that seemed consequent.

Рубрика Философия
Вид статья
Язык английский
Дата добавления 04.03.2020
Размер файла 13,1 K

Отправить свою хорошую работу в базу знаний просто. Используйте форму, расположенную ниже

Студенты, аспиранты, молодые ученые, использующие базу знаний в своей учебе и работе, будут вам очень благодарны.

Размещено на http://www.allbest.ru

Размещено на http://www.allbest.ru

Fichte describes in his The Characteristics of the Present Age (Grundzьge des gegenwдrtigen Zeitalters) a three-stage structure of world history. In the first age of the world the reason stands in instinct and credibility, and therefore the Foundation of the beliefs reached through them, remain hidden from him. This fact, according to Fichte, explains the lack of science in this age. Our age marks the turning point where the rising reason begins. This rise, that is, the liberation of the reason from the form of instinct, is that this age in principle learns the idea of science as a clear understanding of itself. However, this knowledge of his own nature transhistorically this age still do not understand real science, indeed a defining reason, understanding the science is only formally. The new age, that is about to come, will be, according to Fichte, an “epoch of the science of reason” in which philosophy has solved all problems of justification. This will be the very basis for the ongoing systematic progress of science. Despite the undeniable progress that science has made since the time of Fichte this goal has not been achieved to this day. In the essay, I will try to show why this promise of Fichte's “science of knowledge” has not been fulfilled. The answer lies in certain unresolved problems of transcendental philosophy in general and the Fichtian philosophy in particular. Namely, Fichte also failed to completely solve the problem of transcendent schematism, because he did not demonstrate the separation of thought and intuition. In addition, I will indicate a possible solution by surmounting the transcendental schematism.

In his lectures on The Characteristics of the Present Age (Grundzьge des gegenwдrtigen Zeitalters) held for the winter semester of 1804/05, Fichte sums up the spiritual situation of his time as one of “absolute indifference to all truth” [1, S. 11] and as “a state of perfected sinfulness” [1, S. 12]. At first glance this looks as if Fichte is joining the long tradition of lament over the times, which can be traced back to Plato's day or even to the Vedic era of India. However, a brief examination of the concept of history developed by Fichte makes clear that this impression does not do him justice, and that he is not merely bent on discrediting his own age. Rather he aims to grasp the course of history as a process, determined a priori, of the self-unfolding of reason, such that on the basis of this philosophical understanding of history even the deplored state of the present appears as a necessary stage in the evolution of rationality. This process itself obeys the law of Aristotelian dramaturgy, that is, it is divided into five acts in two opposing phases, with a peripateia in the middle, in the third act (cf. [1, S. 8]). Fichte applies this theatrical pattern to the drama of the emergence of perfectible reason, envisioned very much in the manner of Rousseau.

This perfectibility, exemplified both in the phylogenetic and in the ontogenetic series, finds its expression in an overcoming of instinctual nature, stage by stage, as reason comes to itself. The hallmark of this historical process is that it possesses the double stamp of reason in its unity as both theoretical and practical so that Fichte can characterize it as the development of both an increasing determinacy and growing freedom. In the first epoch, the “state of innocence of the human race” [1, S. 11], humanity is in a quasi-infantile, purely instinct-dependent state. As the new instinct of reason seeks to free itself from this primitive instinctual state (cf. [1, S. 9]), the primordial milieu of self-contained humanity is transformed into a second state in which reason acknowledges the necessity of external submission. However, this epoch of authority still does not fulfill the claim of reason to self-determination. With this, the third epoch, the present epoch for Fichte, takes the stage. Here reason frees itself from the instinct of reason itself (cf. [1, S. 9]).

The peculiarity of this transitional epoch is that on the one hand it recognizes the idea of science as a self-penetrating understanding, according to the principle that “nothing is to be accepted as existing and binding except what one understands and conceives clearly” [1, p. 21]. But in this recognition of its own nature, scientific thinking remains merely formal and has not yet raised itself “to the reality of science, of truly determining reason” [1, p. 105]. This holds both for its theoretical and its practical claims and is conditioned by the use of the specific liberative instrument of reason, the concept (cf. [1, S. 21]). Thus, in the epoch of critique, in which reason wins freedom from heteronomous authority, it does not achieve speculative use of its own most concept, the idea. As a result, science cannot wholly embrace its own nature. Science and its object are not yet understood from the principle of their unity, namely reason itself, as “the only possible existence and life that rests on itself and sustains itself, of which everything that appears as existing and living is but the further modification, definition, transformation, and self-shaping” [1, S. 23].

Such a consciousness will be given to reason only in the following fourth “epoch of the science of reason” [1, S. 12], the “state of rising justification” [1, S. 12], in which philosophy further determines itself as a real science, in order to return to itself in the fifth “epoch of the art of reason” [1, S. 12] when it enters “the state of perfected justification and healing” [1, S. 12]. The idea of recovering an initial innocence through the reflected progression of reason, or of humanity`s „going back to the point at which it stood at the beginning” [1, S. 12], again shows a strong imprint of Rousseau, probably mediated by Kant (cf. [3, S. 117 f.; 4, S. 38]).

On the near side of this utopian telos in the circle of the reflection of reason realizing itself in history, the peripeteia of the third, present epoch testifies witness to Fichte`s originality over against Kant and more widely. However, it also points to the central problem of a transcendental philosophy that wants to understand itself systematically, such as Fichte`s doctrine of science certainly is. This problem is that of the transition from the formal to the material determination of science as a philosophy of the real.

From the vantage of the pure science of reason or from a philosophy of the real, the whole field of science is completely surveyed, and what each individual science must perform is determined [1, S. 107].

With this, in the Grundzьge, Fichte unmistakably joins Kant's continuation of the great project of the instauratio magna. We find a very similar formulation in the third and penultimate main section of the Doctrine of Method in the Critique of Pure Reason:

Under the government of reason, our insights must never be rhapsodic but must make up a system, in which they alone can support and promote its essential purposes. By a system, I understand the unity of the manifold insights under an idea [5, A 832-B 850; S. 860].

Fichte sees with great lucidity that this promise of a system of science could be fulfilled neither by Kant himself nor in the aftermath of Kant's philosophy, so that the critical path did not lead through the metamorphosis of “a footpath into an army road” [5, A 856 | B 884; S. 879] to “eternal peace in philosophy” (cf. [3, S. 411ff.; 6, S. 77 ff.]). The reason for this failure lies, as Fichte again clear-sightedly noted in the Prolegomena to the second 1804 lecture course on the doctrine of science (in the same year as the Grundzьge), in the unresolved residual architectural, that is, ontological problem of Kant's system, in that Kant “had first found the actual difference between the supersensible and the sensuous, and now also brought into his absolute the second uninves- tigable quality after its absoluteness, namely that it was the bond of the two worlds” [7, S. 38]. Thus Kant, with Fichte, reaches only a postulated actual point of the unity of his system, which culminates in his substrate doctrine. He combines, and so as it coupled the soberly empirical upshot of his philosophy, for which experience is the beginning of all knowledge, with a supersensible, metaphysically unexplicated element, which gives an opening to enthusiasm -- Schwдrmerei. Here the empirical Zeitgeist dialectically turns into its opposite:

In sum, this may well be the spirit of the particular period of our age in which we live: the system for which sober experience alone is valid may be dying out, while against it we see rising to dominance the system of enthusiasm (Schwдrmerei) that through pretended speculation will banish experience itself from the area which belongs to it alone, with all the consequences destructive to order that this entails, and in order to punish cruelly those who subscribed to the first system. To counteract this onrush is a futile enterprise, for this is the tendency of the times, which is also reinforced with all its other favored inclinations. In this situation, happy is the sage who raises himself above his age and above all time, for he knows that time is nothing at all, and that higher guidance, through all apparent detours, is quite securely leading our species to its true goals! [1, S. 127]

The “apparent detours” were to turn out to be more extensive than Fichte may have guessed. The eternal peace of the republic of scholars as well as the supremacy of transcendental philosophy or the doctrine of science seems today just as remote as in Fichte's time. In terms of Fichte's historical-philosophical approach, we find ourselves still in the third epoch! Many, perhaps even most, contemporary philosophers would probably explain this by saying that Fichte's ideal historical sketch was just wrong and his claims for what philosophy could achieve simply presumptuous. But if we consider Fichte's claim to systematicity with regard to the two realms of being -- nature and culture -- then his ideas do not seem at all far-fetched:

All science that is purely a priori can be completed and its investigations brought to a conclusion, and if only the republic of scholars keeps working on it systematically it will eventually reach this completion. Only the empirical is infinite, whether it be of what is stationary, of nature, in physics, or of what is in flux, the phenomena of the human race, in history. The science of reason, which sifts out all the a priori constituents of physics and perfects them in their particular disciplines and sets them forth in their completed form, then refers physics to experiment and confers on it the art of correctly grasping the meaning of the experiment made, as well as regulative insight into how nature may in each case be further questioned. The same science of reason, abstracts from history the myths about the beginnings of the human race, as belonging to metaphysics, and confers a determinate concept of how history ought properly to ask and what belongs to it, as well as a logic of historical truth: and so even in this infinite realm secure progress according to a rule steps into the place of a random rummaging about [1, S. 107 f.].

What makes this passage so instructive is the way Fichte offers suggestions about the relationship of experience and rational science, seeking to mediate between them along Kantian lines via the regulative a priori, while skipping over the real question, namely the possibility of the constitution of coherence by the regulative. This avoidance of the actual question of epistemology -- how can the determinable be conceived of as itself determinate, if it is determinable in view of a determinate -- is shared by Fichte and Kant. But in contrast to Kant, Fichte takes a further decisive step, in that he marks the leap as such, by raising the comprehension of non-comprehension in the form of the inherent boundary determination of rational science to the highest point of its reflection.

But as far as comprehension itself is concerned, the science of reason establishes as a principle that everything, and even non-comprehension, must be understood as the limit of comprehension and the only possible pledge that comprehension is exhausted; and that indeed in every time, and as the sole bearer of the time, one may encounter such a non-comprehended, something comprehended only as not comprehend -- yet never anything absolutely incomprehensible [1,S. 113].

Fichte's inoculation of incomprehensibility in the system of transcendental philosophy as a noetic transcendence immanent in knowing does seem consequent, but comes with the cost that the doctrine of science as a teaching of unity and splitting, that is, as the theoretical praxis of a logic of grounding and determination, must in consequence expound its highest point as a logic of speculation, but cannot return without a break from this to the particular in the course of the speculative logic of concretion. This is evidenced in the way Fichte, in discussing the deductiveness of the particular, mostly remains remarkably assertoric, without being very convincing (cf. [1, S. 132]).

However, it would be quite misguided to lay this charge only against Fichte himself, since it bears on a grave problem concerning the matter of first philosophy, a problem that has still not been sufficiently clarified. If one looks at the state of the current debates, one observes that these generally do not begin to approach the level of Fichte's grasp of the problem. Both Fichte and Kant engage the problem of given determinacy in a similar way, namely through a theory of schematization:

Knowledge is, as we have said, existence, expression, the perfect image of divine power. It is therefore for itself: Knowledge becomes self-consciousness; and it is for itself, in this selfconsciousness, its own power, freedom and effectiveness, resting on itself, because it is indeed the image of divine power; all this as knowledge, and therefore as evolving through all eternity toward higher inner lucidity of knowing. The knowing refers to a determined object of knowledge from which it takes its departure; this evidently appears as a determinate something, which could also be different, since it is, and yet in its primal ground is not comprehended, but knowing must seek to comprehend it through all eternity, thus developing its own inner power: and it is with this progressive development that time first enters in [1, S. 130 f.].

Fichte's transcendental theory of representation and image differs from Kant's in one essential point: whereas Kant's transcendental schematism is a subsumption-schema that is logically subsequent to a separation of the cognitive faculties, Fichte's schematism is a schema of production or projection that comes before any cognitive achievement. However, Fichte's schematism, too, fails to escape the difficulty of all doctrines of schematism. Just as Kant sets up the mutually determining relationship of intuition and concept at the level of possibility, as determining their relation before the actual schematization of the concept through the application of the logical function to the pure form of the inner intuition, so Fichte, as if mirroring him, presupposes the possibility of their separability at the ground of the unity of knowledge. So if Kant can hardly give a plausible of how thought and intuition are bound together, it is just as difficult for Fichte to demonstrate their separation.

What does this mean for the future of transcendental philosophy? Certainly, the most obvious thing would be to bid farewell to the schematism altogether and to withdraw entirely to the standpoint of dialectic, either with Hegel's heautological dialectic that obtains determinacy by the principle of sublation or with Wolfgang Cramer's heterothetic one, which seeks knowledge of determinacy from the principle of positivity. However, this obvious strategy does not gain traction for two reasons: First, it would at least be necessary, with Hegel, to revise Fichte's insight into the incomprehensibility of the Absolute, and secondly -- a point that weighs heavier in systematic implications -- Hegel's principle of selfconceiving self-grasp always presupposes its claim to validity in its making-itself-valid. That, from a critical point of view, is at best merely thetical, and in the worst case even circular. Likewise, Cramer's transcendental ontology founders in the last instance -- or the first, depending on one's perspective -- on the problem of the ontological determinateness of its problematic ground. Of course, the same can also be said of Nicolai Hartmann's transcendental-realistic standpoint, although Hartmann can certainly be given credit for integrating the problem into his relinquishment of the system in favour of systematics, even though his proposed solution in the form of his categorial analysis remains completely inadequate in terms of transcendental philosophy.

The problem of the third epoch, the transition from formal to material use of the idea within the framework of the science of reason, is thus still not adequately elucidated. This takes nothing of its topicality and explosiveness from Fichte's claim or from Kant's. For this reason alone the debate with them should unreservedly be conducted from a systematic perspective and must just as a topic of philological or historical inquiry. However, this also means that it must be possible to give a systematically convincing answer to the question of the transition. In order to achieve this, it would be necessary to explicate the unity-creating relationship between heautology and heterothetics in such a way that it can identify the possibility of grounding and ordering validity -- and thus the possibility of logical inference -- on the basis of a systematic apriori. However, success in this first requires a coherent, that is, a schematism-free theory of concept and intuition, within the framework of a critical science of knowledge embracing them both, in which the transition from transcendental philosophy to a general theory of system and structure is laid out. Thereby the long-awaited transition to the fourth epoch may come about.

References

fichte epistemology transcendental philosophy

1. Fichte, J. G. (1846), “Grundzьge des gegenwдrtigen Zeitalters”, in Fichtes Werke, ed. Fichte, I. H., Bd. 7, Veit und Comp., Berlin, Prussia, S. 3-256.

2. Oesterreich, P. and Traub, H. (2006), Der ganze Fichte. Die populдre, wissenschaftliche und metaphilosophische ErschlieЯung der Welt, Kohlhammer, Stuttgart, Germany.

3. Kant, I. (1923), Kant's gesammelte Schriften, ed. PreuЯische Akademie der Wissenschaften, Bd. 8, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, Germany.

4. Kant, I. (1999), „MutmaЯlicher Anfang der Menschengeschichte”, in Kant, I., “Was ist Aufklдrung?”, Ausgewдhlte kleine Schriften, Meiner, Hamburg, Germany, S. 28-44.

5. Kant, I. (1998), Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Meiner, Hamburg, Germany.

6. Kant, I. (1999), “Verkьndigung des nahen Abschlusses eines Traktates zum ewigen Frieden in der Philosophie”, in Kant, I., “Was ist Aufklдrung?”Ausgewдhlte kleine Schriften, Meiner, Hamburg, Germany, S. 77-87.

7. Fichte, J. G. (1986), Die Wissenschaftslehre. Zweiter Vortrag im Jahre 1804, Meiner, Hamburg, Germany.

Размещено на Allbest.ru

...

Подобные документы

  • There are valid concepts in TE. Some new concepts of NE are not flawless. The new perspectives enrich our contemplative abilities and knowledge. The fully (for all times) satisfactory definitions or foundations are not likely to be proposed.

    курсовая работа [8,5 K], добавлен 29.11.2003

  • Confucianism as the source of the fundamental outlook for the Chinese. The history of its occurrence during the reign of the Han dynasty. Significant differences of this philosophy from other major canons. Idealistic views on the development of society.

    презентация [889,1 K], добавлен 13.11.2014

  • Why study Indian philosophy. Why study philosophy. The method of asking questions. The Katha Upanishad. The method of analogy. Outline of Indian Philosophy. The Four Vedas. Monism versus Non-dualism. The Epic Period. Sutra Period. The Modern Period.

    презентация [661,8 K], добавлен 26.02.2015

  • Fr. Nietzsche as German thinker who lived in the second half of the Nineteenth Century. The essence of the concept of "nihilism". Peculiarities of the philosophy of Socrates. Familiarity with Nietzsche. Analysis of drama "Conscience as Fatality".

    доклад [15,3 K], добавлен 09.03.2013

  • What is meant by Kant’s "Copernican Revolution"? What is the "Transcendental Aesthetic" about? Explain what Kant means by intuition, pure intuition, empirical intuition; concept, pure concept, empirical concept; transcendent.

    курсовая работа [23,0 K], добавлен 09.04.2007

  • Confucianism as the creation of a harmonious society in the ancient pattern, in which every person has a function. Creativity and the ability of a person to self-renew as a guarantee of human constancy. Methods of constructing harmonious society.

    эссе [14,0 K], добавлен 10.01.2014

  • The Abelards solution of the problem of universals is neither a realistic no a nominalistic one, or, in other words, it is in the same degree nominalistic as it is realistic.

    курсовая работа [23,3 K], добавлен 09.04.2007

  • Initial data for the term paper performance. Order of carrying out calculations. Analyze uncompensated system. Synthesize the real PD-compensator ( ) which would guarantee desired phase margin at gain crossover frequency . Analyze compensated system.

    курсовая работа [658,7 K], добавлен 20.08.2012

  • Buddhism, its history of occurrence and distribution in India and Tibet. His place in world religions. The methods of presentation of religious knowledge and their study followers. The importance of religion in the development of scientific knowledge.

    презентация [758,7 K], добавлен 18.10.2013

  • Basic problems of teenagers in a world. Question of spending their free time, relations with parents and unhappy love. Use for sniffing glue products and solvents. Danger of AIDS, his action on the immune system. Reasons on which are widespread smoking.

    реферат [16,5 K], добавлен 08.02.2010

  • What is Climate. Science is the search for knowledge. Records changes of Climate for period million years. The activity Modern Climate Systems. What is the Greenhouse Effect. The past and current trends in climate change. The way to solve the problem.

    презентация [8,3 M], добавлен 21.02.2011

  • The education system in the United States of America. Pre-school education. Senior high school. The best universities of national importance. Education of the last level of training within the system of higher education. System assessment of Knowledge.

    презентация [1,4 M], добавлен 06.02.2014

  • Testing as a form of control the level of students’ skills and abilities. The classification of tests in learning English. Problems in the control of education. The final results on the evaluation system of knowledge. The main stage of the lesson.

    курсовая работа [37,8 K], добавлен 08.05.2014

  • Everyone lives his own life relying on some ideas, thoughts and some beliefs. Some people call such ideas “philosophy” of life. Even if a person says that he doesn’t live according to some rules or ideas, he defines himself as a follower of such "never-ca

    топик [4,5 K], добавлен 12.11.2006

  • Profession in the USA. Regulation of the legal profession. Lawyers: parasites of the back of the American taxpayer. The legal profession for women: a problem of gender equality. The legal system of the USA. The principles of the USA System of justice.

    курсовая работа [35,9 K], добавлен 31.08.2008

  • The concept of social reality and social fact. Laws and categories of sociology. Structure of sociological knowledge. Levels of sociological knowledge. Macro-sociology and micro-sociology. Fundamental theoretic sociology. Applied empiric sociology.

    реферат [22,4 K], добавлен 29.11.2008

  • Federalism and the Tax System. Federal Taxes and Intergovernmental Revenues. Tax Reform. The Progressivity of the Tax System. Political Influences on the Tax System. Main principles of US tax system. The importance of Social Security taxes.

    реферат [15,9 K], добавлен 01.12.2006

  • Placing the problem of human rights on foreground of modern realization. The political rights in of the Islamic Republic Iran. The background principles of vital activity of the system of judicial authorities. The executive branch of the power in Iran.

    реферат [30,2 K], добавлен 14.02.2015

  • Investigation of the problem with non-local conditions on the characteristic and on the line of degeneracy . The solution of the modied Cauchy problem with initial data. The solution of singular integral equations. Calculation of the inner integral.

    статья [469,4 K], добавлен 15.06.2015

  • The economic benefits to the recipient countries by providing capital, foreign exchange. The question of potential causality between foreign debt and domestic savings in the context of the Kyrgyz Republic. The problem of tracking new private businesses.

    реферат [26,7 K], добавлен 28.01.2014

Работы в архивах красиво оформлены согласно требованиям ВУЗов и содержат рисунки, диаграммы, формулы и т.д.
PPT, PPTX и PDF-файлы представлены только в архивах.
Рекомендуем скачать работу.