Fichte's'empty form of knowledge

The study of the work "The main features of the modern era" Fichte. The interpretation of the "empty form of knowledge", which, he claims, is central to the third era of history. Uniting principles of eras, reflection of differences between principles.

Ðóáðèêà Ôèëîñîôèÿ
Âèä ñòàòüÿ
ßçûê àíãëèéñêèé
Äàòà äîáàâëåíèÿ 17.03.2020
Ðàçìåð ôàéëà 32,3 K

Îòïðàâèòü ñâîþ õîðîøóþ ðàáîòó â áàçó çíàíèé ïðîñòî. Èñïîëüçóéòå ôîðìó, ðàñïîëîæåííóþ íèæå

Ñòóäåíòû, àñïèðàíòû, ìîëîäûå ó÷åíûå, èñïîëüçóþùèå áàçó çíàíèé â ñâîåé ó÷åáå è ðàáîòå, áóäóò âàì î÷åíü áëàãîäàðíû.

Ðàçìåùåíî íà http://www.allbest.ru/

Ðàçìåùåíî íà http://www.allbest.ru/

Fichte's“empty form of knowledge

M. Jorge de Carvalho

This paper deals with Fichte's Grundzüge, and in particular with his discussion of the “empty form of knowledge” he claims stands at the centre of the third -- i.e., the present -- age. Fichte speaks of a fundamental principle that forms the “common denominator” between the third and fourth main epochs. This fundamental principle -- the “maxim of comprehensibility” (Maxime der Begreiflichkeit) -- makes knowledge and comprehension the measure of all that “counts as being valid and as really existing”. But the question arises: How can one and the same principle act as the “unifying concept” for two different “main epochs of human life”? Does this not go directly against Fichte's claim that two main epochs differ from each other in every respect, precisely because they produce two entirely different “unifying principles”, and because everything in them must reflect the difference between their “unifying principles”? Fichte's answer to this question is as follows: a) the fundamental maxim in question allows for two diametrically opposed interpretations, so that each of them provides the principle or the “unifying concept” from which the third and fourth main epochs arise, and b) the third main epoch only gives rise to the empty form of science, as opposed to “truly real science”: it stands for a careless and easy-going, shallow, conventional, trivializing and incorrect conception of the “fundamental maxim of comprehensibility” -- so that it misses what is essential, does not do justice to the fundamental maxim, overlooks its implications, and indeed goes against its innermost meaning.

Keywords: Fichte, Wissenschaftslehre, philosophy of history, form of knowledge, principle.

«Ïóñòàÿ ôîðìà çíàíèÿ» Ôèõòå

Ñòàòüÿ ïîñâÿùåíà ðàáîòå «Îñíîâíûå ÷åðòû ñîâðåìåííîé ýïîõè» È. Ã. Ôèõòå, è â ÷àñòíîñòè åãî òðàêòîâêå «ïóñòîé ôîðìû çíàíèÿ», êîòîðàÿ, ïî åãî óòâåðæäåíèþ, ÿâëÿåòñÿ öåíòðàëüíîé äëÿ òðåòüåé ýïîõè ìèðîâîé èñòîðèè, ò. å. Ôèõòå ãîâîðèò î ôóíäàìåíòàëüíîì ïðèíöèïå, îáðàçóþùåì îáùèé çíàìåíàòåëü òðåòüåé è ÷åòâåðòîé åå ýïîõ. Ýòîò ôóíäàìåíòàëüíûé ïðèíöèï -- «ìàêñèìà ïîíèìàíèÿ» (Maxime der Begreiflichkeit) -- äåëàåò çíàíèå è ïîíèìàíèå ìåðîé âñåãî, ÷òî ñ÷èòàåòñÿ äåéñòâèòåëüíûì è ðåàëüíî ñóùåñòâóþùèì. Íî âîçíèêàåò âîïðîñ: êàê ìîæåò îäèí è òîò æå ïðèíöèï êàê «îáúåäèíÿþùåå ïîíÿòèå» áûòü ôóíäàìåíòàëüíûì äëÿ äâóõ ðàçíûõ «îñíîâíûõ ýïîõ ÷åëîâå÷åñêîé æèçíè»? Íå ïðîòèâîðå÷èò ëè ýòî ïðÿìî óòâåðæäåíèþ Ôèõòå î òîì, ÷òî äâå ãëàâíûå ýïîõè îòëè÷àþòñÿ äðóã îò äðóãà âî âñåõ îòíîøåíèÿõ èìåííî ïîòîìó, ÷òî îíè ïðîèçâîäÿò äâà ñîâåðøåííî ðàçíûõ «îáúåäèíÿþùèõ ïðèíöèïà», è ïîòîìó, ÷òî âñå â íèõ äîëæíî îòðàæàòü ðàçëè÷èå ìåæäó èõ «îáúåäèíÿþùèìè ïðèíöèïàìè»? Îòâåò Ôèõòå íà ýòîò âîïðîñ òàêîâ: à) ðàññìàòðèâàåìàÿ ôóíäàìåíòàëüíàÿ ìàêñèìà äîïóñêàåò äâå äèàìåòðàëüíî ïðîòèâîïîëîæíûå èíòåðïðåòàöèè, òàê ÷òî êàæäàÿ èç íèõ äàåò ñâîþ âåðñèþ ïðèíöèïà, èëè «îáúåäèíÿþùåãî ïîíÿòèÿ», èç êîòîðûõ è âîçíèêàþò òðåòüÿ è ÷åòâåðòàÿ îñíîâíûå ýïîõè ìèðîâîé èñòîðèè; è á) òðåòüÿ ýïîõà ïîðîæäàåò òîëüêî ïóñòóþ ôîðìó íàóêè, â ïðîòèâîïîëîæíîñòü èñòèííî ðåàëüíîé íàóêå, ïåðâàÿ îçíà÷àåò íåáðåæíîå è ëåãêîå, ïîâåðõíîñòíîå, óñëîâíîå, òðèâèàëüíîå è íåïðàâèëüíîå ïîíèìàíèå «ôóíäàìåíòàëüíîé ìàêñèìû ïîñòèæåíèÿ» -- òàêèì îáðàçîì, îíà óïóñêàåò ñóùåñòâåííîå â ïîçíàíèè, íå îòäàâàÿ äîëæíîãî ôóíäàìåíòàëüíîé ìàêñèìå, óïóñêàåò èç âèäó åå ñëåäñòâèÿ è äàæå âûñòóïàåò ïðîòèâ åå ãëóáî÷àéøåãî ñìûñëà.

Êëþ÷åâûå ñëîâà: Ôèõòå, íàóêîó÷åíèå, ôèëîñîôèÿ èñòîðèè, ôîðìà ïîçíàíèÿ, ïðèíöèï.

This contribution deals with Fichte's discussion of the “empty form of knowledge” he claims stands at the centre of the third -- i.e. the present -- age.

First, let us recall that Fichte's “philosophical picture of the present age” [1, S. 196] involves an attempt to deduce “the main epochs of human life on earth” (cf. [1, S. 197]) from a single principle, or rather from a “unifying concept of the entire human life on earth”, which “can be clearly comprehended in its unity, and from which the main epochs of human life on earth can be fully deduced and clearly understood, both in their origin and in their connection with each other” (cf. [1, S. 197]). According to Fichte, this “unifying concept of the entire human life on earth” consists in humankind being able to “order all its relations with freedom according to reason” (cf. [1, S. 198]). That is, it consists in freedom “appearing in the entire consciousness of the species” and emerging “as its own freedom, as a true and actual deed and as a product of the species in its own life, proceeding from its own life” (cf. [1, S. 198]). This freedom-oriented goal forms the all-encompassing connection in which every essential aspect of human life and every significant turn of events can be integrated.

Let us recall, moreover, that Fichte's entire conception of the “main epochs of human life on earth” hinges on the claim that, “according to the basic idea presented, mankind's life on earth is divided into two main epochs or ages”: “one in which the species lives and exists without as yet having ordered its relations with freedom according to reason; and another in which this rational ordering is accomplished” (cf. [1, S. 198-199]). The first main epoch is a precondition for the second one, insofar as complete freedom cannot be merely given, but must come about as something self-acquired -- i.e. as the result of a kind of self-liberation or self-release -- and requires, therefore, a preliminary stage or starting point (the “whereof”, so to speak, without which there can be no self-liberation or selfrelease).

But this is not all. Fichte also points out that the transition from the first to the second main epoch cannot come about immediately. Since the first main epoch is characterized by the absolute domination by a blind drive or instinct, it leaves no room for the transition to the opposite state of freedom (cf. [1, S. 199-200]). According to Fichte, this transition is impossible without the intervention of two mediating elements, namely:

1. an epoch in which “the results of the rational instinct [des Vernunftinstinkts] (...) are made into an external ruling authority, upheld through coercive means (...) by the strongest individuals of the species, in whom -- precisely on account of their strength -- that instinct speaks in its loudest and broadest tones” (cf. [1, S. 200]), so that it takes the form of a “coercive authority” (cf. [1, S. 200]), i.e. a form that differs from absolute or “unconditional authority” (cf. [1, S. 201]) (from the “soft coercion of personal instinct” (cf. [1, S. 200])); and

2. an epoch in which the “drive to free oneself from rational instinct” (cf. [1, S. 200]) gains the upper hand and “rebels against the pressure of a foreign instinct that interferes with one's own right; and through this awakening it breaks the chains, not of rational instinct in itself, but of the instinct of foreign individuals, which has taken the form of an external source of coercion” (cf. [1, S. 200]).

The first of these two “mediating elements”, or “transitional ages”, corresponds to a kind of attenuated form of instinct (cf. [1, S. 243]) Diejenige, da dieser Instinct, schwächer geworden, und nur noch in wenigen Auserwählten sich aussprechend, durch diese wenigen in eine zwingende äußere Autorität für Alle verwandelt wird., which, by introducing a distance between the individual and “externalized” instinct, so to speak, provides the track switch leading to the revolt against instinct perceived as a “foreign authority”, or as “coercion” -- and therefore also to the second mediating element. The latter is characterized, in turn, by generating a preliminary form (or a weak, ill-conceived, immature form) of freedom, which falls far short of freedom's full development. According to Fichte, the latter can only be attained in the fourth, or even in the fifth main epoch.

Let us recall, finally, that the succession of stages we are talking about reveals two main aspects expressly emphasized by Fichte.

The first one relates to the fact that the different epochs under consideration are also distinguished by the role they ascribe to the species, or the individual. The “rational in-stinct” that permeates the first main epoch “refers (...) only to the relations and the life of the species, and by no means to the life of a mere individual” (cf. [1, S. 210]). The same also applies to the second main epoch, but in such a way that the “rational instinct” relating to the species is for most individuals no longer the “soft coercion of personal instinct” (cf. [1, S. 200]). Rather, it takes the form of an external coercive authority, or of a “blind faith and unconditional obedience” (cf. [1, S. 201]). The third main epoch, which frees itself from rational instinct, is characterized, on the contrary, by “not letting absolutely anything count as real” “other than the life of the individual and whatever relates or refers to it” (cf. [1, S. 210]). According to Fichte, the fourth (and a fortiori the fifth) main epoch is characterized, on the contrary, by bringing about a reversal of this development. For “rational instinct -- and indeed reason in any of its forms -- embraces only the life and relations of the species” (cf. [1, S. 210]).

The individual (or the fact that the individual takes over the leading role and becomes the centre around which everything else revolves) is thereby an essential condition for the emergence and the discovery of freedom as such. This does not mean, however, that the species no longer plays any part. On the contrary, according to Fichte, reason and species are found to belong to each other in an essential way, so that the aim of human life on earth (i.e. humankind's ability to “order all its relations with freedom according to reason”) implies restoring the primacy of the species. And this is what Fichte's fourth and fifth main epochs are all about.

The second main aspect of the succession that is expressly emphasized by Fichte has to do with the fact that each main epoch is characterized by a specific relationship with knowledge and cognition. The first main epoch, which acts as the precondition or the starting point for self-liberation or self-release, is characterized by the unbounded coercion of personal instinct. It translates into a dark drive or a blind coercion (the “soft coercion” of personal instinct) that is not in the least related to insight, knowledge, or the like. The same applies to the second main epoch, which differs from the first one in that in its case the authority of instinct takes the form of the external ruling and coercive authority of foreign individuals or that of “blindfaith and unconditional obedience”. The third main epoch is characterized, on the contrary, by the fact that its “release from instinct” is intimately tied to the “creation of science” (Erzeugungder Wissenschaft) (cf. [1, S. 199]). As Fichte emphasizes, the third main epoch is “the epoch of release (Befreiung): an immediate release from the external ruling authority, and a mediate release from the power of rational instinct and from reason in general, in any of its forms” (cf. [1, S. 207]). Its essence is the discovery or the emergence of freedom as freedom (of the fact that freedom as such emerges and takes over the leading role). In short: this epoch is characterized by having the notion of freedom as its cornerstone.

The crucial point here is the essential connection between freedom and knowledge. The discovery or emergence offreedom as freedom entails the discovery or the emergence of knowledge as knowledge. Or rather, as one might also put it, the concept of freedom relates to the concept of knowledge in such a way that the former presupposes the latter. The self-liberation or self-release takes the form of a drive to rebel “against the pressure of a foreign instinct, which interferes with one's own right” (cf. [1, S. 200]). That is to say, the self-release is directed both against the instinct and against what is foreign -- and “knowledge” is the weapon, as it were, it resorts to against both.

Of great importance in this context is the interweaving of the two concepts in question (and especially the fact that the concept of freedom presupposes, by its very nature, the concept of knowledge). Equally important is the fact, related to the previous one, that the release around which the third main epoch revolves -- namely, the release from the “foreign authority” or from the “external coercion” -- invokes the concept of knowledge or appeals to this concept (so that it devises knowledge as such and what is required by it). In other words, the said release carries high the flag of knowledge, so to speak -- and thereby knowledge not only emerges, but is also granted, together with freedom, the main role.

Yet there is also a third point that is no less important, namely the fact that the concept of knowledge that hereby emerges is only a preliminary form (or a weak, ill-conceived, immature form) of this concept, which falls far short of its full development. According to Fichte, the latter can only be attained, in the fourth main epoch. This is another characteristic aspect of the doctrine presented by Fichte: the essential connection between freedom and knowledge also translates into the fact that both the realization of freedom and the realization of knowledge begin with a flawed development, so to speak. To “empty freedom” (leereFreiheit) (cf. [1, S. 209]) corresponds an “empty knowledge” (leeres Wissen).

We will see below that this fact determines the form and direction of Fichte's “philosophical picture of the present age”. For now, however, the question of why the concept of freedom starts by assuming -- or must assume -- an ill-conceived and defective form, which Fichte terms “empty freedom”, will not occupy us any longer. We will concentrate on Fichte's discussion of “empty knowledge” and the reason why the concept of knowledge, too, must start by appearing as an ill-conceived and defective concept.

1. The “fundamental maxim of comprehensibility” and its two diametrically opposed conceptions or interpretations, which underlie the third and fourth main epochs. The contrast between the “empty form of science” and “truly real science”

So much for the preliminary remarks. They delimit the scope of this paper and allow us to understand what the third “main epoch of human life on earth” is about, and why Fichte can claim that the principle or the fundamental maxim that characterizes this main epoch runs as follows: “(...) to accept as being and binding absolutely nothing other than what one can understand and comprehend clearly” (cf. [1, S. 209]). This fundamental maxim, to which comprehending (Verstehen, Begreifen), comprehensibility and knowledge are the alpha and omega, is supposed to give rise, according to Fichte, to the “unifying concept” where from everything else -- i.e. all other essential features and characteristic phenomena of the third (that is, the present) main epoch -- derives.

At first glance, then, it seems quite amazing to see Fichte add, immediately afterwards, that the very same principle also underlies the fourth main epoch of human life on earth: “Regarding this fundamental maxim, -- taken exactly as we have enunciated it, without any further specification, -- this third main epoch is entirely equal to the one that must come after -- the fourth one, the epoch of rational science, -- and precisely through this equality paves the way for it. From the standpoint of science, as well, nothing but what is comprehensible is deemed valid” (cf. [1, S. 197]). But the question arises: How can one and the same principle, or the same fundamental maxim act as the “unifying concept” for two different “main epochs of human life”? Does this not go directly against what Fichte writes about the “monadic” character of the main epochs: namely, that two main epochs differ from each other in every respect, precisely because they produce two entirely different “unifying principles”, and because everything in them must reflect the difference between their “unifying principles” -- or, to borrow Leibniz's words, the difference between their “monadic identities”?

On closer inspection, however, this objection is found to rest on a misunderstanding. For Fichte also points out, emphatically, that the fundamental maxim in question allows for two diametrically opposed conceptions or interpretations, and that each of them provides the principle or the “unifying concept” from which the third and fourth main epochs arise: “Only with the application of this principle (in Absicht der Anwendung dieses Princips) is there this contrast between both ages, [namely] that the third -- which we shall call, for now, simply the age of empty freedom -- makes its fixed and pre-existing comprehension (sein stehendes, und schon vorhandnes Begreifen) the measure of being; while the age of science, on the contrary, makes being the measure, not of the comprehension (Begreifen) that is already available, but of that it is required to achieve (keineswegs des ihm schon vorhandnen, sondern des ihm anzumuthenden Begreifens). To the former, there is nothing other than what it already comprehends; the latter seeks to comprehend, and does comprehend -- all there is. The latter, the age of science, penetrates with its concept everything without exception, even that which remains absolutely incomprehensible, [in that it penetrates it]as incomprehensible; [it penetrates] the first, the comprehensible, to put in order the relations of the species; it penetrates the second, the incomprehensible, in order to be sure that the realm of comprehensibility has been exhausted, and that it has taken possession of the limits of comprehensibility. The former, the age of empty freedom, knows nothing of the fact that only with effort, diligence and skill can one learn to comprehend. Instead, it possesses a certain repertoire of concepts, and an established common sense already at hand, which it inherited without the least effort; and it uses these concepts and this common sense as the measure of what counts as being valid and as really existing (als den Maafistab des geltenden und seyenden). It has a great advantage over the age of science: it knows everything without ever having learned anything and can thus pass judgement on whatever comes before it, immediately and without further ado, with no need for preliminary enquiries” (cf. [1, S. 209]).

We will limit ourselves to the main point.

To begin with, Fichte speaks of a fundamental principle that forms the `common denominator, as it were, between the “unifying principles” of the third and fourth main epochs. This fundamental principle, which he also terms the “maxim of comprehensibility”(Maxime der Begreiflichkeit) (cf. [1, S. 282]), makes knowledge and comprehension the measure of all that “counts as being valid and as really existing”. That is, comprehension (Begreifen) or comprehensibility (Begreiflichkeit) is the standard whereby everything is measured (the basis on which everything stands, the form which everything must acquire). All that “counts as being valid and as really existing” must prove to be knowledge and comprehension (to be the correlate of knowledge and comprehension). As something justified and legitimized by knowledge and comprehension. Otherwise, it is deemed null and void.

However, this `common denominator' -- the “maxim of comprehensibility” -- takes on two opposite forms. And so it happens that the third and the fourth epochs have a `common denominator' while remaining, nonetheless, toto coelo different. Fichte speaks of two “applications” of the fundamental maxim in question. One should not forget, though, that at stake here are neither a) two applications that only differ from each other because they refer to different fields of application (in such a way that the applied fundamental maxim remains unchanged), nor b) two equally legitimate applications, that fulfil the fundamental maxim to an equal extent, and are therefore equally valid. On the one hand, Fichte wishes the “applications” in question to be understood as two opposite conceptions or interpretations of the fundamental maxim, according to which comprehension and comprehensibility stand for very different things, so that the common denominator itself (i.e. the “fundamental maxim of comprehensibility”) becomes something different. On the other hand, Fichte also emphasizes that the two opposite conceptions or interpretations in question exhibit a sharp `difference in quality, as it were, and that one of them is defective. In the 8th Lecture, he writes: “(...) for this [the age of rational science] The 4th main epoch, and hence also the second conception of the “maxim of comprehensibility”. does not in any way reproach this maxim of comprehensibility in and for itself, -- rather, it recognizes it as its own; what it does reproach is only the erroneous and unsuited concept underlying this mode of comprehension and converted into the measuring standard for everything valid” “(...) denn dieses [das Zeitalter der Vernunftwissenschaft] tadelt keineswegs jene Maxime der Begreiflichkeit an und für sich, -- es erkennt sie vielmehr an als ihre eigene; sondern es tadelt nur den schlechten und untauglichen Begriff, der bei diesem Begreifen zum Grunde gelegt und zum Massstabe aller Gültigkeit gemacht wird” (underlining added). Incidentally it should be noted that this passage from the 8th lecture is actually meant to describe how the fourth main epoch views the third. But one must not forget that Fichte intends the fourth main epoch to be understood as the remedy for the insufficiency of the third (and, in particular, for the insufficiency of its understanding of the “fundamental maxim of comprehensibility”) -- so that its view of the third main epoch also coincides with Fichte's own claims. Perhaps we can borrow one of Fichte's expressions and speak of the “determining ingredients” (die bedingenden Ingredienzien) of comprehension and knowledge as such (cf. [1, S. 195]). (cf. [1, S. 282]).

But how do the two opposite conceptions or interpretations of the “fundamental maxim of comprehensibility” differ from each other?

The first one tacitly presupposes a pre-existent sphere of comprehension and knowledge, which is not to be questioned, and makes this established comprehension (or rather this alleged comprehension) the standard whereby everything else is measured. It fails to raise the question concerning the essence of comprehension (Begreifen and Wissen) as such and lets itself be guided by a pre-existing concept of comprehension. The concept of comprehension that decides everything is, therefore, itself already pre-decided, as it were, and everything is subordinated to the authority of what is already pre-decided -- or in the stranglehold of what is already pre-decided.

The second conception or interpretation of the fundamental maxim follows a completely different approach. It lets itself be guided by the question of what is required for comprehension (Begreifen) as comprehension or for knowledge (Wissen) as knowledge: what, according to its own nature, must belong to it(the high threshold that must be met in order to achieve real Begreifen or real Wissen). To “comprehend” stands here for the totality of conditions or requirements intrinsic to this concept (for the programme inherent in it, or the work description it gives rise to -- in short, for the set of specifications proper to the concept of comprehension): what must be attained if there is to be any comprehension (Begreifen) or knowledge (Wissen).5 From this it follows 1. that this conception of the “maxim of comprehensibility” is in no way presupposed (it assumes nothing, it presupposes nothing) and must start from scratch; 2. that it checks everything -- not least all apparent comprehension and all apparent knowledge- to see whether it corresponds to the essence of comprehension and knowledge as such and whether it meets the conditions and requirements in question; and this is done in such a way that 3. this conception of the “maxim of comprehensibility” does not merely find out what it takes a) for a minimum of actual comprehension (Begreifen), or b) for an all-encompassing comprehension (Begreifen). Rather, it is also committed to fully undertaking what is thus brought out -- i. e. the programme contained in the very concept of comprehension or knowledge.

The difference between the two conceptions or interpretations of the “maxim of comprehensibility” that are at stake here can also be summed up as follows: in the first case, the pre-established sphere of comprehension is broadened in such a way that that which is added to it and incorporated in it must be compatible with the pre-existing comprehension, or similar to it; what is more, it must have the form of the pre-established comprehension; in the second case, on the contrary, all pre-established and alleged comprehension must be compared with, and measured against, that which is required by the concept of comprehension and knowledge according to its own nature. That is to say, everything must take on a form pursuant to the “work description” inherent in comprehension as such.

Fichte summarizes the contrast between the first and the second conception of the fundamental maxim in the following way: “What I, through the concept that is immediately present within me, do not comprehend, is not, says the empty freedom; what I, through the absolute concept that has become its own end, do not comprehend, is not, says science” (cf. [1, S. 209]). This contrast can also be summed up by a variation of a well-known dictum by Baco of Verulam Neque enim arctandus est mundus ad angustias intellectus (quod adhuc factum est), sed expandendus intellectus et laxandus ad mundi imaginem recipiendam, qualis invenitur [2, S. 397]. [2, S. 397]): the first conception of the “maxim of comprehensibility” (namely, that which underlies the third main epoch) amounts to claiming that everything ad angustias intellectus arctandum (where “intellectus” stands for comprehension in its immediate form I. e., for the “fixed and pre-existing comprehension” (stehendes, und schon vorhandnes Begreifen) or for the comprehension that is “already at hand” (schon fertig, und bei der Hand) [1, S. 209].), whereas the second conception (i.e. the “unifying principle” of Fichte's fourth main epoch) understands the “maxim of comprehensibility” to the effect that the intellectus (i.e. all comprehension) expandendus et laxandus ad ideam intellectus recipiendam, qualis invenitur (where “idea intellectus” stands for everything that is required by comprehension or knowledge as such -- for a minimum of actual comprehension or knowledge just as much as for full comprehension and knowledge).

It is therefore no accident that Fichte terms the first conception of the “maxim of comprehensibility”(and therefore, at the same time, the “unifying principle” of the third main epoch) the “empty form of science”: “this age is, therefore, in its own separate existence, [the] concept of the concept, and has the form of science; but in fact only the empty form thereof, since it lacks that through which alone science is given a content, namely the Idea” (cf. [1, S. 247]). Fichte underlines both a) that the third age becomes acutely aware of comprehension(of the concept, of knowledge, of science) and indeed so much so that comprehension as comprehension (knowledge as knowledge, science as science -- or, as Fichte says, Begriff des Begriffes:the “concept of the concept” (cf. [1, S. 247]) moves to the centre; and b) that that which the third main epoch thus moves to the centre only gives rise to the empty form of science (the empty form of knowledge, the empty form of the concept) -- in short, that the whole is afflicted with a kind of emptiness. Fichte stresses this point in various places, speaking of the empty form of science (leere Form der Wissenschaft) (cf. [1, S. 247]), of empty formal knowledge (leeres formales Wissen) (cf. [1, S. 281]), of “formal science” (formale Wissenschaft) (cf. [1, S. 255, 259, 260, 262]) and of the “formalism of the bare irrational concept"(Formalismus des blossen vernunftlosen Begriffs) (cf. [1, S. 276]) as opposed to “truly real science” (wahre reale Wissenschaft) (cf. [1, S. 251]).

But what does “empty”, in this case, mean? First of all, it means that the form of knowledge in question (the form of science, of comprehension or of the concept) lacks the appropriate content, precisely because the third age has no appreciation for what Fichte terms the “Idea”.8 But this is not all. The emptiness that is at stake here must also be put down to the fact that, even though the form of knowledge is placed in the centre, the relationship with it remains fundamentally superficial: it does not penetrate its essence, and indeed misses the main point altogether. In other words, the problem does not lie simply in that the form in question is not “fulfilled” as it should be: it lies also in that the form itself (the form of comprehension, or the form of knowledge) is basically not taken seriously enough: it is diluted or watered-down, as it were; it is submerged or blocked, or only apparently considered. Put differently, the problem comes down to two facts. On the one hand, it comes down to the fact that the first conception of the “maxim of comprehensibility” has no idea of what it takes to achieve real Begreifen or Wissen (of all the requirements that must be met by comprehension or knowledge viz. of all that is entailed in the very form or in the very concept of comprehension or knowledge). On the other hand, the problem comes down to the fact that, in the end, the unifying principle of the third main epoch only gives rise to a careless and easy-going, shallow, conventional, trivializing and incorrect conception of the “fundamental maxim of comprehensibility” -- so that it misses what is essential, does not do justice to the fundamental maxim, overlooks its implications, and indeed goes against its innermost meaning9.

This cannot be stressed enough: it is not as if the conception of the form itself were correct, and only the appropriate content were lacking -- it is not as if the form in question (the very form of Begreifen and Wissen) were empty only in this particular sense. It is rather that the conception of the form itself is defective. Herein lies the main point: The form itself is grossly mistaken, and therefore, in this sense, empty. That which is regarded as the form of knowledge and cognition is not the genuine form of knowledge and cognition -- it is not the true “concept of the concept” (Begriff des Begriffes)! As it turns out, it only generates the correlate of an incorrect perception of the form of knowledge and cognition. And from this it follows that Fichte's third main epoch does not stand for an actual supremacy of the concept, but only for its seeming supremacy -- namely, for the supremacy of the empty concept.

This is also connected to the reason why Fichte terms the third main epoch the “state of complete sinfulness” (Stand der vollendeten Sündhaftigkeit) (cf. [1, S. 207]). It goes with- Or because this age is quite simply “incapable of the Idea” (der Idee unfähig ist). Cf. 254. On Fichte's understanding of what he terms Idea (cf. [1, S. 235, 244, 287]). All of this can be summed up as follows: The conception of the “fundamental maxim of comprehensibility” underlying the third main epoch is afflicted by the fact that the form of comprehension and knowledge does not become an Idea, in the Fichtean sense. And this, in turn, relates to the fact that the Leichtnehmen (viz. the `lightheartedness') discussed in the 5th lecture (cf. [1, S. 249]) -- i.e. the flaw of taking things too lightly or too easily -- also hinders the understanding of the fundamental maxim itself. out saying that this characterization has to do with the supremacy of the individual -- and that Fichte means above all the sin of egoism -- i.e. a sin in the `moral'sense. This is also why the second main epoch (which has nothing to do as yet with“empty formal knowledge”) is called the “state of mounting sin”(Stand der anhebenden Sünde) (cf. [1, S. 201]). One must not forget, however, that Fichte's description of the third main epoch concerns above all a cognitive `sin' (a `sin' against the concept, or a `sin' against the true form of comprehension): the `sin' of “empty formal knowledge” (i. e. the `sin' of the empirical way of thinking, the “art of thinking away incessantly” (cf. [1, S. 201]), etc.). It is thus no exaggeration to speak of two `sins', closely connected to one another -- or of a double `sinfulness'.

2. A third essential element of “empty formal knowledge”:

the “natural drive for self-preservation and personal well-being”.

Fichte's claim about the double nature of “empty formal knowledge”.

The sphere of the secondary, indifferent and non-binding form of what

“is and counts as valid”

But this is still not all. A further element now comes into play. What has been described as the first conception of the “fundamental maxim of comprehensibility” is also characterized by something else, which is equally decisive for the nature of the third main epoch. This further trait relates to the fact that the suppression of the power of instinct, which triggers the transition from the second to the third main epoch, falls far short of a complete removal of all instinct. As mentioned earlier, this suppression takes the form of a refusal of all foreign, external ruling authority and leaves a core of personal instinct untouched, namely the instinct that refers to individual life: the instinct that Fichte terms the “mere natural drive for self-preservation and personal well-being” (blossen Naturtrieb der Selbsterhaltung und des persönlichen Wohlseyns) (cf. [1, S. 201]).

Here, two elements are equally important: a) that the release from instinct leaves behind a sort of residuum, and b) that the remaining part of instinct revolves around the “existence and well-being” (Daseyn und Wohlseyn) of individual life. But something else is also important: This remaining core of instinct is characterized, among other things, c) by the fact that it entails a sphere of alleged Begreifen or comprehension (i.e. something like a knowledge claim), and last but not least d) by the fact that it can (and indeed tends to) play the role of the pre-established comprehension or knowledge tacitly presupposed by the first interpretation of the “fundamental maxim of comprehensibility”. That is to say: The sphere of immediate evidence that corresponds to this drive is the one that can act (and indeed tends to act) as the “fixed and pre-existing comprehension” (cf. [1, S. 209]) which the first interpretation of the “fundamental maxim of comprehensibility” “uses as the fixed measuring standard Viz. the reliable measuring standard. for all that is and counts as valid” (als den sicheren Maasstab alles seyenden und geltenden anwendet) (cf. [1, S. 212]).

This adds a final touch to the picture of the third age and its underlying maxim. Fichte's third age possesses a double nature, so to speak. It rests both a) on what we have termed the careless and defective conception of the “fundamental maxim of comprehensibility”, and b) on a kind of “primary moving principle” (Grundtriebfeder), (cf. [1, S. 212]) namely, on the continual “drive for self-preservation and well-being” (cf. [1, S. 212]) -- or, as Fichte also writes, on the drive “to promote self-preservation and personal well-being to the greatest possible extent”(die Selbsterhaltung und das persönliche Wohlseyn möglichst zu befördern) [1, S. 213].

Fichte himself emphatically highlights the double nature of the third age and speaks of two premises: “Firstly, the fundamental maxim of the age, as indicated above, is now further determined; and it is clear that from its established premise -- `What I do not comprehend is not' -- there must immediately follow this other: `Then I do not comprehend anything whatsoever other than that which concerns my personal existence and well-being;11 and hence there is nothing more than this; and the whole world really only exists for this reason: that I should exist and feel good. Whenever I do not understand how something relates to this end, that something is not, and does not concern me” [1, S. 213]. Yet the reference to two premises must not make us lose sight of the fact that Fichte is actually speaking of the “fundamental maxim of comprehensibility” and of two additional elements, which modify the fundamental maxim in such a way that 1. the latter is viewed through the lens of the aforementioned “ill-formed and unsuited”(schlechten und untauglichen) conception, which uses an alleged comprehension, pre-existing and ready to use, as the measuring standard of comprehensibility (cf. [1, S. 376]); and 2. the role of the alleged, pre-existing comprehension (whereby everything that “is and counts as valid” is measured) is played by a knowledge claim stemming from a specific drive or instinct12.

This particular characteristic of the “unifying principle” that gives rise to the third main epoch enables us to dispel a possible misunderstanding. Fichte speaks of the third main epoch as the “age of absolute indifference to all truth, and of complete and absolutely unguided freedom”13 (Zeitalter der absoluten Gleichgültigkeit gegen alle Wahrheit, und der völligen Ungebundenheit ohne alle Leitfaden) [1, S. 201, 207]. But what is this supposed to mean? And how does it relate to the previous description?

The statement in question does not necessarily mean that in the third main epoch all knowledge is basically indifferent, and that absolutely nothing of what counts as “being” or “valid” is binding. It is already clear that in the realm of Fichte's third stage one's personal situation, one's “own existence and well-being”, together with everything that is meaningful to one's existence and well-being -- and hence also the core of drive-related or instinct-related knowledge claims (the alleged Begreifen of one's own situation, and of what is at stake in it), which tacitly acts as a measuring standard -- is by no means indifferent or non-binding. For the pressure of the “natural drive for self-preservation and personal well-being” makes such an indifference and such a freedom absolutely impossible. The indifference and freedom of which Fichte speaks refer only to the remaining knowledge, to the remaining comprehension, to the remaining part of “what counts as being valid and as really existing”. It refers, therefore, to that which lies outside of the said core or centre -- i.e. to the opinions of the third main epoch about what appears to have no actual or significant effect on personal “existence and well-being”.

To be sure, this point is not specifically highlighted by Fichte. But it should be borne in mind that his description of the maxim underlying the third main epoch is tantamount to saying a) that everything is divided into two regions of “what counts as being valid The second premise. Namely, the knowledge claim entailed in the “mere natural drive for self-preservation and personal well-being” [1, S. 207, 210]. “Boundlessness” or “independence”. and as really existing” (cf. [1, S. 209]), and b) that the second region revolves, as it were, around the first one, forming a kind of periphery. What is essential here is that all remaining knowledge (all knowledge other than the knowledge of what has a significant effect on one's personal “existence and well-being”), along with the remaining part of “what counts as being valid and as really existing”, stands under the aegis of personal “existence and wellbeing' (i. e. of its knowledge) and is completely subordinated to it. We can speak, therefore, of an additional, secondary and second-rate knowledge, or rather of an additional, secondary and second-rate version of “what counts as being valid and as really existing”. What appears to be irrelevant to personal “existence and well-being” counts only as a further determination of that which, in its essence (i. e. with regard to personal “existence and well-being”), is already determined. And indeed, no such further determination is ever regarded as essential and binding -- it is basically indifferent.

And so it happens that Fichte's discussion of the “whole system of thought and opinion” (des gesammten Denk = und Meinungs = Systems)14 of the third main epoch deals primarily with science, art, politics, morality and religion (cf. [1, S. 215-216]), insofar as they belong to this subordinated -- indifferent and non-binding -- sphere of “what counts as being and valid”. Indeed, the original feature of all that belongs to the “system of thought and meaning” in question One could also speak of the whole opinion-system (or of the whole system of beliefs) of the third main epoch (cf. [1, S. 243, 258]). The defining feature that gives rise to all others. consists precisely in its being reduced to playing this subordinated (non-binding, indifferent) role Our discussion of “empty formal knowledge” does not focus on the different `figures' -- the drama-tis personae, or the `main characters', as it were, of the third main epoch (its science, its art, its politics, its morality, its religion, its writers, its books, its critics, its readers, etc.) -- which Fichte examines gradually and with great care. We turn our attention away from these different `characters' and seek rather to outline the structural features that form their `common denominator'..

So much for Fichte's discussion of the double nature of the third age, or rather of the two main components determining its essence.

3. The misunderstood form of knowledge as an essential requirement for the emergence and development of the very form of knowledge But there is still a particular point that is worth highlighting.

Fichte's main focus lies in a sort of ambiguity of the fundamental maxim -- in the ambiguity due to the fact that the “fundamental maxim of comprehensibility” (i. e. one and the same fundamental principle) can be interpreted in two opposite senses and thereby legitimize two wildly different attitudes and perspectives Namely the opposite conceptions and the wildly different attitudes and perspectives that are characteristic of Fichte's third and fourth main epochs.. In other words, Fichte emphasizes two different points. On the one hand, he claims that the form of knowledge is bound to emerge sooner or later, and indeed to take over the leading role and become the central concept around which everything else revolves. On the other hand, he also claims that the said central concept (the “Begriff des Begriffes”) starts by appearing in an empty form --e. in an ill-conceived, immature, misunderstood or distorted form.

This main point can also be expressed in the following manner. Fichte's fundamental claim about the necessary historical development goes hand in hand with the view that the concept of knowledge (viz. what he terms the “concept of the concept”)emerges in certain, precisely defined circumstances, which strongly influence the shape it takes. His discussion of the third main epoch aims to show that the form of knowledge or cognition -- i. e. “the concept of the concept” -- is not discovered and does not become the central concept in a neutral medium. It happens, rather, that the form of knowledge and cognition is discovered (or must be discovered) and becomes the central concept in a medium that is bound to distort it considerably and to reduce it to a shadow of itself.

This misunderstood form of knowledge and cognition is characterized a) by overlooking the essential implications of the maxim of which it is made up of, so that the form of knowledge or cognition does not fully develop and is not understood in all its fullness; b) by placing the concept of knowledge under the aegis of a presupposed knowledge (i. e. of an alleged knowledge that is immediately available), which is used as the standard of measurement of everything else; c) by the fact that this presupposed knowledge is determined by a drive, for it is nothing other than the cognitive claim that emerges from (and is inherent in) the “drive for self-preservation and personal well-being” So that the form of knowledge and cognition (the “concept of the concept”, etc.) falls prey to this drive, which leaves its mark on it.. And this, in turn, means that d) the form of knowledge and cognition is initially seen through this “lens” or “filter” (through this “double filter”: the frivolous and defective conception of the form and the boundless authority of the drive for “self-preservation and personal well-being”). The genuine form of knowledge and cognition is thus blocked, as it were, and indeed so much so that e) the misunderstood form of knowledge becomes self-evident and remains completely ignorant of its peculiar nature (of its double nature, of its wrongness, etc.) and of every possible alternative.

Fichte thus holds that thisgradual development of the form of knowledge or cognition is essential: that the form of knowledge must start by appearing as the empty form of knowledge (as a distorted and incorrect form), and that only a further development, which takes the “empty” form as a starting point and reacts against it, can lead to the full development of the concept of knowledge, or of the form of knowledge as such. In other words: by its very nature, the emergence and discovery of knowledge must occur in two stages. It requires as a precondition something like a flawed development: a defective conception of the form of knowledge (a defective “concept of the concept”). Fichte's point is that this defective “concept of the concept” lies, as it were, in the very nature of things. And this is the reason why there must be not only the first and the second main epochs(and immediately afterwards the fourth Which in that case would be the third one. And indeed, because it reveals, as one might also put it, a “necessary educational stage” of knowledge itself (of Begreifen viz. Wissen).)but also a third, acting as a mediating element or transitional stage between the second and fourth main epochs. Conclusion: the empty form of science- “empty formal knowledge”, “formal science”, the “formalism of the bare irrational concept” -- is a “necessary stage in human education” (nothwendige Bildungsstufe der Menschheit)20 so “that our species also has to crossit” (dass unsere Gattung eben auch da hindurchmüsse)

fichte empty form knowledge

Ðàçìåùåíî íà Allbest.ru

...

Ïîäîáíûå äîêóìåíòû

  • There are valid concepts in TE. Some new concepts of NE are not flawless. The new perspectives enrich our contemplative abilities and knowledge. The fully (for all times) satisfactory definitions or foundations are not likely to be proposed.

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [8,5 K], äîáàâëåí 29.11.2003

  • Why study Indian philosophy. Why study philosophy. The method of asking questions. The Katha Upanishad. The method of analogy. Outline of Indian Philosophy. The Four Vedas. Monism versus Non-dualism. The Epic Period. Sutra Period. The Modern Period.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [661,8 K], äîáàâëåí 26.02.2015

  • Confucianism as the creation of a harmonious society in the ancient pattern, in which every person has a function. Creativity and the ability of a person to self-renew as a guarantee of human constancy. Methods of constructing harmonious society.

    ýññå [14,0 K], äîáàâëåí 10.01.2014

  • Confucianism as the source of the fundamental outlook for the Chinese. The history of its occurrence during the reign of the Han dynasty. Significant differences of this philosophy from other major canons. Idealistic views on the development of society.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [889,1 K], äîáàâëåí 13.11.2014

  • Postmodernists also argue that other characteristics of modern societies are disappearing. Ðostmodernism is anti-foundationalism, or anti-worldview. Separation is the alpha and omega of the spectacle.

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [16,4 K], äîáàâëåí 12.02.2003

  • Recent studies conducted by psychologists, philosophers and religious leaders worldwide. The depth of love. The influence of behavior on feelings. Biological models of sex. Psychology depicts love. Caring about another person. Features teenage love.

    ðåôåðàò [59,9 K], äîáàâëåí 20.01.2015

  • Fr. Nietzsche as German thinker who lived in the second half of the Nineteenth Century. The essence of the concept of "nihilism". Peculiarities of the philosophy of Socrates. Familiarity with Nietzsche. Analysis of drama "Conscience as Fatality".

    äîêëàä [15,3 K], äîáàâëåí 09.03.2013

  • Testing as a form of control the level of students’ skills and abilities. The classification of tests in learning English. Problems in the control of education. The final results on the evaluation system of knowledge. The main stage of the lesson.

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [37,8 K], äîáàâëåí 08.05.2014

  • In the world there are thousands of different languages. How indeed modern English is optimum mean for intercourse of people of different nationalities. Knowledge of English is needed for the effective teaching subsequent work and improvement of our life.

    ñî÷èíåíèå [13,7 K], äîáàâëåí 11.02.2009

  • The role of constitutional principles in the mechanism of constitutional and legal regulation. Features of transformation in the interpretation principles. Relativism in the system of law. Local fundamental justice in the mechanism of the state.

    ðåôåðàò [24,7 K], äîáàâëåí 10.02.2015

  • Buddhism, its history of occurrence and distribution in India and Tibet. His place in world religions. The methods of presentation of religious knowledge and their study followers. The importance of religion in the development of scientific knowledge.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [758,7 K], äîáàâëåí 18.10.2013

  • A critical knowledge of the English language is a subject worthy of the attention of all who have the genius and the opportunity to attain it. A settled orthography is of great importance, as a means of preserving the etymology and identity of words.

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [28,1 K], äîáàâëåí 14.02.2010

  • Data mining, developmental history of data mining and knowledge discovery. Technological elements and methods of data mining. Steps in knowledge discovery. Change and deviation detection. Related disciplines, information retrieval and text extraction.

    äîêëàä [25,3 K], äîáàâëåí 16.06.2012

  • The applied science model. The basic assumptions underlying this model. Received and experiential knowledge. Oldest form of professional education. The most advanced modern teaching strategies. Projects for the development of creative abilities.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [156,0 K], äîáàâëåí 09.03.2015

  • The main theories in the field of human origin, their basic content and direction of research. Basic stages of human development from the primitive to the modern form of the form. Character change erectus skeleton human time frame of the process.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [614,1 K], äîáàâëåí 26.09.2014

  • The concept of social reality and social fact. Laws and categories of sociology. Structure of sociological knowledge. Levels of sociological knowledge. Macro-sociology and micro-sociology. Fundamental theoretic sociology. Applied empiric sociology.

    ðåôåðàò [22,4 K], äîáàâëåí 29.11.2008

  • The concept and essence of democracy as a system of government, the basic elements, main definitions. The history of democracy: from ancient Greece to the present day. The main principles of democracy. The advantages and disadvantages of democracy.

    ðåôåðàò [28,0 K], äîáàâëåí 12.08.2011

  • Direction of professional self - development. Features of emotional sphere. Personal qualities of the social teacher and teacher of self-knowledge. The concept of vital functions as a continuous process of goal-setting, operations and human behavior.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [2,5 M], äîáàâëåí 08.10.2016

  • The basic tendencies of making international educational structures with different goals. The principles of distance education. Distance learning methods based on modern technological achievements. The main features of distance education in Ukraine.

    ðåôåðàò [19,1 K], äîáàâëåí 01.11.2012

  • Defining cognitive linguistics. The main descriptive devices of frame analysis are the notions of frame and perspective. Frame is an assemblage of the knowledge we have about a certain situation, e.g., buying and selling. Application of frame analysis.

    ðåôåðàò [324,4 K], äîáàâëåí 07.04.2012

Ðàáîòû â àðõèâàõ êðàñèâî îôîðìëåíû ñîãëàñíî òðåáîâàíèÿì ÂÓÇîâ è ñîäåðæàò ðèñóíêè, äèàãðàììû, ôîðìóëû è ò.ä.
PPT, PPTX è PDF-ôàéëû ïðåäñòàâëåíû òîëüêî â àðõèâàõ.
Ðåêîìåíäóåì ñêà÷àòü ðàáîòó.