The epistemological glaucoma and psematical paradox (autological feature of truth and heterological feature of false)

Consideration of the main arguments of the deflationary concept of truth, characterization of the approaches of A. Tarsky, W. V. Quine, H. Putnam. Deflation of "truth" with necessity require deflation of "false". Arising at the elimination of false.

Ðóáðèêà Ôèëîñîôèÿ
Âèä ñòàòüÿ
ßçûê àíãëèéñêèé
Äàòà äîáàâëåíèÿ 19.04.2021
Ðàçìåð ôàéëà 26,5 K

Îòïðàâèòü ñâîþ õîðîøóþ ðàáîòó â áàçó çíàíèé ïðîñòî. Èñïîëüçóéòå ôîðìó, ðàñïîëîæåííóþ íèæå

Ñòóäåíòû, àñïèðàíòû, ìîëîäûå ó÷åíûå, èñïîëüçóþùèå áàçó çíàíèé â ñâîåé ó÷åáå è ðàáîòå, áóäóò âàì î÷åíü áëàãîäàðíû.

Ðàçìåùåíî íà http://www.allbest.ru/

The epistemological glaucoma and psematical paradox (autological feature of truth and heterological feature of false)

A.N. Pavlenko

Institute of Philosophy of RAS

Abstract. In this paper is considered the main arguments of the deflationary concept of truth: the approaches of A. Tarski, W.V. Quine, H. Putnam and some others. Here are presented two representative examples of the elimination of truth as the value of the proposition: the concept of “languages games” by L. Witgenstein and “constructive empiricism” by B. van Fraassen. It is revealed that the statement “there are no true statements” is self-predictive and leads to absurdity. It is demonstrated that the elimination of “truth” from epistemology will require, with necessity, the elimination of “false” also. It is shown, that when we try to get answer on the question “Can a “false sentence”, understood as a “not true” sentence, i.e. - ð, has the same denotation on which it denotes (not be true)” a paradox arises, which calls “psematic” from the Greek word ^spara (false). The essence of the paradox is that “every false sentence denotes false” denotes every false sentence denoting false, if and only if, “every false sentence denoting false” is not every true sentence denoting the truth. The result is: a) if “every false sentence denoting false” itself is not every true sentence denoting the truth, then, by the definition of “every false sentence denoting false”, it is not a sentence denoting false. And vice versa: b) If “every false sentence denoting false” itself is every true sentence denoting the truth, then, consequently, it is “every false sentence denoting false” and it is a sentence denoting false.

In any case, it turns out that the proposition “false sentences denote false”, simultaneously have the sign that they designate and do not have it. It was found that “truth” has an autological nature, and “false” has heterological one.

Key words: psematical paradox, truth, false, epistemology, ontology, constructive empiricism, lanquage games, G. Frege, A. Tarski, W.V. Quine, H. Putnam psematical paradox truth false

Ãëàóêîìà ýïèñòåìîëîãè÷åñêàÿ è ïñåìàòè÷åñêèé ïàðàäîêñ (àâòîëîãè÷íîñòü èñòèíû è ãåòåðîëîãè÷íîñòü ëæè)

À.Í. Ïàâëåíêî

Èíñòèòóò ôèëîñîôèè ÐÀÍ

 ðàáîòå ðàññìîòðåíû îñíîâíûå àðãóìåíòû äåôëÿöèîííîé êîíöåïöèè èñòèíû: ïîäõîäû À. Òàðñêîãî, Ó.Â. Êóàéíà, Õ. Ïàòíåìà è íåêîòîðûå äðóãèå. Ïðèâåäåíû äâà ðåïðåçåíòàòèâíûõ ïðèìåðà ýëèìèíàöèè èñòèíû êàê âûäåëåííîé îöåíêè ñóæäåíèé: êîíöåïöèÿ «ÿçûêîâûõ èãð» Ë. Âèòãåíøòåéíà è «êîíñòðóêòèâíûé ýìïèðèçì» Á. âàíÔðààññåíà. Âûÿâëåíî, ÷òî óòâåðæäåíèå î òîì, ÷òî «„èñòèíû“, êàê âûäåëåííîé îöåíêè ñóæäåíèé, íå ñóùåñòâóåò» ÿâëÿåòñÿ ñàìîïðåäèêàòèâíûì è ïðèâîäèò ê íåëåïîñòè. Ïðîäåìîíñòðèðîâàíî, ÷òî ýëèìèíàöèÿ (èçáûòî÷íîñòü) «èñòèíû» èç ïîçíàíèÿ, ñ íåîáõîäèìîñòüþ, çàòðåáóåò è ýëèìèíàöèþ «ëæè». Ïîêàçàíî, ÷òî ïðè îòâåòå íà âîïðîñ “ìîæåò ëè «ëîæíîå ïðåäëîæåíèå», ïîíèìàåìîå êàê ïðåäëîæåíèå «íå èñòèííîå», òî åñòü - ð, îáëàäàòü òåì ïðèçíàêîì, êîòîðîå îíî îáîçíà÷àåò êàê îáúåêò «ëîæü», òî åñòü «áûòü íå èñòèííûì»?”, âîçíèêàåò ïàðàäîêñ, êîòîðûé íàçâàí «ïñåìàòè÷åñêèì» îò ãðå÷åñêîãî ñëîâà óåðàø (ëîæü). Ñóòü ïàðàäîêñà â òîì, ÷òî à) åñëè «âñÿêîå ëîæíîå ïðåäëîæåíèå, îáîçíà÷àþùåå ëîæü» ñàìî íå ÿâëÿåòñÿ âñÿêèì èñòèííûì ïðåäëîæåíèåì, îáîçíà÷àþùèì èñòèíó, òî îíî, ïî îïðåäåëåíèþ «âñÿêîãî ëîæíîãî ïðåäëîæåíèÿ, îáîçíà÷àþùåãî ëîæü» -- íå ÿâëÿåòñÿ îáîçíà÷àþùèì ëîæü.È, íàîáîðîò, á) Åñëè «âñÿêîå ëîæíîå ïðåäëîæåíèå, îáîçíà÷àþùåå ëîæü» ñàìî ÿâëÿåòñÿ âñÿêèì èñòèííûì ïðåäëîæåíèåì, îáîçíà÷àþùèì èñòèíó, òî, ñëåäîâàòåëüíî, îíî ÿâëÿåòñÿ «âñÿêèì ëîæíûì ïðåäëîæåíèåì, îáîçíà÷àþùèì ëîæü», è îáîçíà÷àåò ëîæü. ëþáîì ñëó÷àå ïîëó÷àåòñÿ, ÷òî ñóæäåíèå «ëîæíûå ïðåäëîæåíèÿ îáîçíà÷àþò ëîæü» îäíîâðåìåííî è îáëàäàåò òåì ïðèçíàêîì, êîòîðûé îíî îáîçíà÷àåò, è íå îáëàäàåò èì. Îáíàðóæåíî, ÷òî «èñòèíà» îáëàäàåò àâòîëîãè÷åñêîé ïðèðîäîé, à «ëîæü» -- ãåòåðîëîãè÷åñêîé.

Êëþ÷åâûå ñëîâà: ïñåìàòè÷åñêèé ïàðàäîêñ, èñòèíà, ëîæü, ëîãèêà, ýïèñòåìîëîãèÿ, îíòîëîãèÿ, êîíñòðóêòèâíûé ýìïèðèçì, ÿçûêîâûå èãðû, Ã. Ôðåãå, À. Òàðñêèé, Ó.Â. Êóàéí, Õ. Ïàòíåì

1. STATEMENT OF PROBLEM

As it often happens, the discussion of the problem of the existence of truth began simply: a question was asked about what meaning we put in the statement that “the sentence p is true”? How can any proposal be true? The answer was that: the sentence p istruewhenwhatissaidinthesentenceofnaturallanguageisreallythere. Such a correspondent answer goes back to the definition of truth given by Aristotle in Metaphysics [2]:

“To say of what is that it is not, or of what is not that it is, is false, while to say of what is that it is, and of what is not that it is not, is true” (Met.1011b25).

Modern logic, striving for the accuracy of expression, pays attention to what to say that “it is true that p” means simply to say p. Alfred Tarski insisted that the natural language is not strict enough, and therefore Aristotle's definition of truth must be

expressed logically strictly with the help of the equivalence: “the sentence `snow is white' (p) is true ifandonlyif the snow is white”. In this case, it turns out thattruthisexactlywhattheequivalenceitselfis. It turns out that “truth”, as a characteristic of the sentence, isredundant, because in this sentence there is an equivalence. But, further, Tarski notes: “In consequence, if we wish to say something about a sentence, for example, that it is true, we must use the name of this sentence, and not the sentence itself” [18. P. 344]. In other words, the left part of the statement mentioned above can be interesting.

W.V. Quine doubted this and noticed that in the first part of the sentence exactly what is contained in the second one is reported. Therefore, it is necessary to disquoted the first part, and we will get a simple tautology. In the name of the proposal -- that is, in the quoted expression “snow is white” -- there is absolutely nothing that is not in the sentence itself that the snow is white. Therefore, the predicate of truth is nothing more than the procedure of disquoting the first part of the sentence [16. P. 10].

In other words, the truth becomes redundant in our knowledge, turning into a “quoting sentence”, then into an “equivalence”, then into something else. But since the truth -- and to this leads its deflation -- becomes redundant, then, consequently, we cannot say about any of our statement that it “is true”. And, finally, then comes the most important point -- the whole world threatens to turn into our “words game”.

In fact, H. Putnam in one of his works “Brains in a Vat” [15] stated that if 1) our signs do not correspond in reality to what we designate, 2) our images do not correspond to anything in reality that we imagine, 3) Finally, our notions do not correspond to anything in reality, which we are trying to grasp conceptually, then, consequently, the whole world that surrounds man is a completeillusion. So, Putnam believed, skepticism is born. To overcome it, he proposed his famous argument, acting as an “honest skeptic”, that is, Putnamtriedtoovercomeskepticismnotfromtheoutside (from the point of view of another concept), but fromwithin. Here, in my opinion, is his main merit on the issue under discussion.

We have already turned to the analysis of his argument “Brains in a Vat” in another papers [12; 13], so we will not dwell on this in details.

We admit that such criticism of the “truth” named above and some other philosophers [1; 3--5; 10; 14] leaves one important question missing: well, “truth” does not exist -- it is redundant, it deflates, etc., but the “false” is there or a fallacy -- is also our illusion? And if we say “yes”, in what sense? This question does not seem trivial any more. In other words, let us try to investigate the nature of falsehood precisely as an object of semantics and epistemology.

2. GLAUCOMA EPISTEMOLOGICAL

2.1 Deflation of “truth” with necessity require deflation of “false”

The Researchers, who adhere to the concept of deflation of “truth” [10; 16--18], in fact, face one unexpected consequence for them, the essence of which follows. If we will normatively understand by “truth” and “false” the allocated values of sentences or in other versions -- “the conditions for their acceptability”, so we cannot disagree with the fact that “truth” and “false” are correlative notions. In their relationship, “truth” is not removable without eliminating “false” and “false” -- without eliminating “truth”. “False” cannot be eliminated even with the fact that it will be understood as a “negation of the truth”.

If this is so, then the assertion of supporters of the deflationary concept of truth, believing that “truth” as the value of our knowledge, is eliminated from epistemology, will necessarily have to admit an elimination of “false”, unless they are convinced fallibilists, who believe that our knowledge is only a fallacy.

However, if we eliminate and “false”, then, thereby, we open the door for chaos. After all, if there is no truth in knowledge, no false, then this very knowledge of ours has no difference from the singing of birds or the noise emitted by a paddle blow against the water?! Then, everything we do is just footprints on the sand and, consequently, our efforts are vain. But in this case, we cease to be “the eyes of this world”.

In this regard, let us allow ourselves one analogy. Imagine that there is a huge Universe, which is a huge organism, and people in it are its “eyes”, with which it sees itself. After all, in the human body, the eyes are just a very small part of the whole organism. But in importance they immeasurably surpass many other organs. Using this analogy, one could say that without our, without human, knowledge, the Universe would be “blind”!

NotethattheUniverse, from the physics-cosmological point of view, willstaythesameasitwas, butblind. After all, a person deprived of vision, from the physics- chemical point of view, does not differ from a person who is sighted.

But then both fallibilism and the deflationary concept of truth are something like “eye glaucoma ” in ontology and epistemology. However, we are treating a biological glaucoma!? And we treat successfully. So why does “glaucoma epistemological” reserve the right of “incurability”? Let's try to find ways and approaches to its treatment.

2.2 “Second-Order” Fallacy

Let's consider one more general question. Very often we come across the criticism of some concepts -- by others, who believe that their critically acclaimed concepts are entitled to such criticism. That means that representatives of these concepts believe that they themselves and shared by them views are “above” or figuratively speaking -- on the “second floor” from the height of which they can easily criticize the concepts of the lower one. Apparently, they implicitly believe that their own concepts are related to “the second order” of complexity. There is a natural question: on the base of what does it arise?

To answer this question, we give two representative examples that we have discussed yet. [11, Ch. 2].

Firstexample. The preconditions for the appearance of a “second-order fallacy” can be found, for example, in L. Wittgenstein's “Philosophical Studies”, where a model of “language games” was presented [19]: “7. We can also think of the whole process of using words in (2) as one of those games by means of which children learn their native language. I will call these games `language-games' and will sometimes speak of a primitive language as a language-game. And the processes of naming the stones and of repeating words after someone might also be called language-games”.

His reasoning in “Philosophical Research” Wittgenstein begins with the analysis of the language: the procedures of designation and naming. Considering the use of words in natural language, he gradually leads the reader to the idea that the system of meanings of names that Frege proposed was confronted with semantic and pragmatic difficulties. Frege believed that the meaning of names are the objects they designate: “A logically complete language (Begriffsschrift) should satisfy the conditions, that every expression is grammatically well-constructed as a proper name out of the signs already introduced in fact designate an object, and that no new signified as a proper name without having a referent assured. The logic books contain warnings against logical mistakes arising from the ambiguity of expressions. I regard as no less pertinent a warning against the apparent proper names with no referents” [8. P. 222]. However, Wittgenstein specifically selects such cases -- for example, the case with the magic sword of Notung from “The Song and the Nibelungs” -- when a name cannot be associated with any object as its meaning, while admitting that the pointed sword does not exist as a whole, but only as a set of parts: the handle, the blade, etc. As a result, it turns out that Frege's demand is excessively strict or simply unrealizable.

But, how then to act with names with which we cannot immediately and directly compare the object? Does this mean that they are all ambiguousnames or pseudo-names, as Frege suggested? [8. P. 222]. No, Wittgenstein finds a way out of this “impasse of naming” by referring to the domain ofusingofnames: “43. For the large numbers of cases, we do not know the meaning of “meaning can be defined thus: themeaningofthewordisitsuseinthelanguage (italics my-4P)”. And if so, then the truth is just a proper use of a name in a language. In this definition of Wittgenstein, the key is the predicate “to be use in language”.

And here it is impossible not to pay attention to the self-predictability of this statement. In fact, if one strictly follows this definition of Wittgenstein's “meaning”, then we will have to admit that the meaning of thename "useinthelanguage ”isan "object ” thatdependsontheusein a language, and therefore does not exist “l i m i t e d” of use in a language, therefore, the definition is incorrect. The fact is that puttingthevalueof a nameindependencewiththeuseinthelanguage, we forget that the definition itself, given by Wittgenstein, is also “use in the language”, that is, we make it “relative”, referred to the language. Being related to something ceases to fulfill some universal significance. HereWittgensteincommitshisfirstepistemologicalyawn, believing that he is on the “second floor”.

However, this approach is also not entirely simple. Because language is natural, it contains an unimaginable variety of uses. How in this case to avoid chaos? For the correct naming Wittgenstein introduces the notion of a language “paradigm”, in which cultural or social context is easily recognized, that means certainnormsfortheuse of linguistic expressions (Fragments 55--58).

The fear of losing a paradigm prompts us to seek reflexively some clarity and certainty in the language. We naively believe that it is internally logically ordered, as Frege thought, “105. When we believe that we must find that order, must find the ideal, in our actual language, we become dissatisfied with what are ordinarily called `propositions', `words', `signs'. The proposition and the word that the logic deals with are supposed to be something pure and clear-cut. And we rack our brains over the nature of the real sign or the idea at the present moment?”

But is it so? Is there a genuine logical language? Wittgenstein believes that this is one of the main fallacies of the European tradition of thinking. Why? He gives an explanation: “107. The more narrowly we examine the actual language, the sharper becomes the conflict between it and our requirement. (For the crystalline purity of logic was, of course, not the result of the investigation: it was a requirement.) The conflict becomes intolerable; the requirement is now in danger of becoming empty. --We have got on to slippery ice where there is no friction and so in a certain sense. We want to walk: so, we need friction. Backtotheroughground!(italics my -- A.P.)”. What is this “rough ground”? What is its nature? Wittgenstein finds it in the field of human real needs: “The preconceivedideaof crystalline purity can only be removed by turning out our whole examination round. One might say: the axis of reference of our examination must be rotated, but about the fixed point of our real need” (Fragment 108). Wittgenstein consciously commits a philosophical turn, abandoning the soil of “strict” logic and revealing the basis for further philosophizing inthedailyuseoflanguage(Fragment 116).

Then he says: “118. Where does our investigation get its importance from, with it, it seems only to destroy everything interesting, that is, all that is great and important? (It was all the buildings, leaving behind only bits of stone and rubble.) What we are destroying is nothing but housesofcards(italics my -- A.P.) and we are clear”.

As “houses of cards” of Wittgenstein there is an any form of rational explanation, coupled with logic. In such destruction, the end justifies the means, because “120. When I talk about language (words, sentences, etc.) I must speak the language of every day”.

Here we are faced, for the second time, with Wittgenstein's “epistemological yawn”. Indeed, declaring that only "houses of cards” are being destroyed, Wittgenstein silently eludes the question of whether his own concept of "an everyday use of language” and "language games” (and the destruction of house of cards behind it) is just as accurate houses of cards?The answer arises by itself -- of course, it is.

Secondexample. Another illustrative example is the concept of “the constructive empiricism” of Bas van Fraassen, who also believes that he has proclaimed a new program called Constructive Empiricism -- CE [6; 7]. The basic statements of the CE on an issue under discussion were as follows:

1. Theories speak not about truth, but about facts.

2. Facts are described by empiricalstatements.

3. The purpose of science is to formulate theories that are empiricallyadequate.

4. Adoption of the theoryimplies only beliefthat the theory is empirically adequate.

5. The theory is empirically adequate if its consequencesareobservable.

We see that van Fraassen eliminates the truth from the explanation of scientific knowledge, replacing it with “adequacy”. Strikingly, as if following by Wittgenstein, van Fraassen reduces the establishment of “adequacy” to the communicative community, with the only difference from the first, that by Wittgenstein the community communicates on “everyday language” and by van Fraassen's on “scientific language”.

In addition, van Fraassen does not justify sufficiently adequacy of his “adequacy” to modern natural science, which he talks about in his main work [6].

So, the conclusion that arises after considering the “second-order” concepts is simple: theirauthorsthinkthattheirmodels (concepts) arecertainlytrueoradequate.

In other words, my argument reduces to the fact that:

-- anydeflationaryconceptthatdeniesoreliminatesthetruth, itself -- foritsownself-affirmation -- mustassumeitself “true”. After all, otherwise, the deflationary concept of “truth” itself falls under its own assertion “there are no true statements” or somewhat stricter and in Fregian sense -- “truth” as an object does not exist. Obviously, here we deal with self-predictability. After all, if “true sentences” or “truth the object of true sentences” do not exist, then, consequently, this very sentence is not true (does not point to such object as “truth”). But, if this sentence is “false” then it is true, etc. We come to a difficulty resembling the “paradox of a liar”. Elimination of truth from reasoning and valuation of sentences often leads to its confusion with lies. Remembering that “false” in Greek is called yspaxa (psemata) and the “truth” is called a^pGsia (aleteya), we call such mixed concepts “aletopsematical”, and the very tendency on such mixture -- “aletopsematism”.

For me, another side of this problem is also interesting: what will happen if we stand up on a side of an advocate of deflationary concept that allows the redundancy (absence) of truth in our evaluation of the proposals and assume that there are not only “true proposals” but also “false proposals”. Such conclusion he cannot prevent. So, what do we get in the end?

3 “THE PSEMATICAL PARADOX”, ARISING AT THE ELIMINATION OF FALSE

So, the followers of the deflationary model of truth believe that, having easily coped with the task of eliminating “truth” from knowledge and describing the world, they finally solved the most difficult problem for them -- need to include truth as a value of propositions in a communicative discourse or in a community of “constructive empiricists” -- inherited from the antiquity to the modern empiricists and fallibilists. However, I think they are completely unaware that, having coped with one problem, they immediately face another, much more complexed and difficult.

After eliminating the “truth” from the knowledge, they will have with the need to eliminate “false”. But this, in my opinion, leads to an obvious absurdity, to be more exact -- to a paradox that resembles the heterological paradox [17].

Here we introduce Frege's classical assumption [9. P. 205], which he has provided in form of two theses, that:

(I) .Every true sentence denotes the truth,

(II) .Every false sentence denotes the false.

and, relying on it, we will outline the essence of the problem.

To demonstrate this difficulty, consider two types of sentences:

(1) “True sentence”, in Frege's sense, is a sentence that itself has that sign (“to be true”), which it designates as an object.

Otherwise, i.e. in the case of not recognizing it as true, we would have to admit that the “true sentence”, which “denotes truth as an object”, is itself not true, which is obviously absurd. In other words, the statement “every true sentence denotes the truth” cannot be not true.

Thus, it turns out that Frege's assertion (I) is essentially autological in the sense of L.Nelson and K.Grelling [17. P. 338--384].

Now consider the second type of sentence -- “false”, which we define, as logic demands, through negation of “true sentences”, that is, as is customary in modern analytic philosophy, denoting the “true sentence” by the symbol p, and the “false sentence” bynegating the symbol denoting the true sentences of -- p and giving a definition:

(2) A “false sentence " is not a true sentence, that is, -- p.

Now we will give these definitions a more complete form:

(A) The sentence that “true sentences have the feature of `being true'” is a sentence in which some term p (“true sentence”) itselfhasthatfeatureof X (“tobetrue"), whichitdesignates as an object. Non-recognition of this, as we noted above, leads to absurdity.

Consequently, according to the definition of false sentences (2), it turns out that the sentence “every false sentence denotes a false” should look like this:

(B) “Any non-true sentence (- p) denotes non-truth 1 X”.

The question arises: canititselfbetrue? The answer seems to be self-evident: of course, it can, because it is a sentence of the metalanguage and there is no need to apply to it the values of the object language. But, what confuses us here? I think -- the following: the truth, as it seems to me, precisely in the sense of Frege -- as an ideal object -- is autological, and the false is not.

In other words: everything that is inherent the truth is true. This is clearly seen with the thesis (I) of Frege.

In fact, with the proposition -- “true sentences possess the sign of “being true”, represented in the form of:

Question (a): “Can the proposition `a true sentence which denotes the truth' be true?"

problems do not arise: it is obvious that the true sentence is therefore true, when has the feature that the object designated by it has -- “to be true”.

But in the second case, there arises a difficulty of logical property: can a “false proposition” possess the sign that it designates, that is, “not be true”. Or somewhat stricter in form of:

Question (p): “Can the proposition `a false sentence which denotes the false' be false?"

Immediately there can arise an objection to the incorrectness of such assertion, since in the Frege's statement there is a matter of metalanguage, and the metalanguage is not obliged to possess the properties of an object language, that is, of the language about which the metalanguage is proposed -- such an ideal object as “truth” or “false”. It seems to be all right. But if this is so, then we cannot say anything definite about the statement (I). After all, then it turns out that it also “hangs in the air”, because it does not possess the property of the object pointed to -- “to be true”. As we noted above regarding assertion (I) -- in this case it turns out to be absurd.

Note that this question is very similar to the question in the heterological paradox: “can the notion `heterological' be heterological?” [20].

After all, if “truth” as “an object of true sentences” doesnotexist, then, consequently, this very our sentence is not true (does not point to such an object as “truth”), unless we understand the truth in the object language and metalanguage in different meanings.

Further we agree to understand under the quoted statement (II) of Frege “every false sentence denotes false” -- onlythenameofthatfalsesentence, which denotes false. At the same time, the unquoted expression that everyfalsesentencedenotesfalse we will regard as an object judged by the sentence-name (quoted).

Having agreed on this, we will give our expression a stricter form in accordance with the definition of false sentence (2), which says that “False sentence” is not a true sentence, that is, “- p”. In the end, we get:

The sentence "every false sentence denotes false” denotes every false sentence denoting

false, if and only if, "every false sentence denoting false” is not a sentence denoting

the truth.

Now, instead of expression “denoting the truth”, we substitute the definition of a sentence denoting the truth. As a result, we get:

The sentence “every false sentence denotes false” denotes every false sentence denoting false, if and only if, “every false sentence denoting false” is not every true sentence denoting the truth.

The result is the following:

a) if “every false sentence denoting false” itself is not every true sentence denoting the truth, then, by the definition of “every false sentence denoting false”, itisnot a sentencedenotingfalse.

and vice versa,

b) If “every false sentence denoting false” itself is every true sentence denoting the truth, then, consequently, it is “every false sentence denoting false” and itis a sentencedenotingfalse.

In any case, it turns out that the proposition “false sentences denote false”, simultaneously have the sign that they designate and do not have it. As a result, we come to the paradox: “false sentences at the same time have the sign `to be false (not true)' (- p) and do not have them (- - p)”, or, given that (- - p = p) in formal expression:

- p ^ p

We see that we were led to this difficulty by the answer to the question (P).

This paradox suggests that false judgments:

a) considered not just as human propositions, namely ontologically -- are phantoms (from the Greek ^dvraopa (phantasma) -- a ghost).

b) have a heterologicalnature because the proposition “Every false sentence denotes false” cannot be false.

By the analogy with critics of the heterological paradox that we find in von Wright's work [20], one could say that the definition of a false sentence through the negation of a true sentence is incorrect, sincetheabsenceof a signisnotitself a sign, but in that case, we find ourselves in an even more difficult situation: after all, all modern logic isliterallybased on an understanding of “false” exactly how “denying the truth”. And that objection, voiced by von Wright, which passes with respect to the heterological paradox, does not pass in the case of a paradox that I would call “psematical”, from the Greek yspara -- “false”.

There are no references to false sentences, they do not point to anything, just as Putnam's “Brains in a Vat” cannot point to anything. But, thus, the world of false sentences delimits the world of true sentences, which, in the case considered above, themselves have a sign of the object to which they point. Or very briefly: it is impossible to agree with Frege in this matter -- suchobjectas “false” simplydoesnotexist.

The result is an amazing conclusion: a false, paradoxically -- in a literal and figurative sense -- saves the truth.

REFERENCES

[1] Anisov AM. The formal epistemology. The problems of Reality and Truth. Epistemology: the perspectives of evolution. M.: Kanon+, 2012. (In Russ).

[2] Aristotle, Metaphysics // Collected works in 4 volumes, Moscow, 1976, V. 1, 550 p. (In Russ).

[3] Armour-Garb, B. `Horwichian Minimalism and the Generalization Problem', 2010. Analysis 70 (4): 693--703.

[4] Ayer AJ. `The Criterion of Truth' -- Analysis, v. 3, No. 3, Jan. 1936. Pp. 28--29.

[5] Ayer A.J. Language, Truth, and Logic. 2nd ed. L., 1946. Ch. 5.

[6] Fraassen BC. van. The Scientific Image, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980.

[7] Fraassen BC. van. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Science', in Churchland and Hooker, 1985, pp. 245--308.

[8] Frege G. Sense and reference. The Philosophical review. Volume 57, Issue 3 (May 1948).

[10] Horwich P. Truth. Oxford, 1998, 176 p.

[11] Pavlenko A. The Limits of Intersubjectivity (A Critical View on the Communicative Ability for the justification of Knowledge). SPb., 2012, 278 p. (In Russ).

[12] Pavlenko A. Theorem about “back of the head”. Skepsis; 2004. XVII; 210--224.

[13] PavlenkoAndrey. Skepticism against skepticism. Proceedings of the XXII World Congress of Philosophy, Korea, 2008. p. 205--216.

[14] Pavlov SA. Basis Statements of the Truth Theory with the Truth Operator. Bulletin of Peoples ' Friendship University of Russia, Series Philosophy. 2009 (3): 100--113. (In Russ).

[15] Putnam H. Reason, Truth and History. Cambridge University Press, 1981, 236 p.

[16] Quine WV. Philosophy of Logic. Englewood Cliffs Prentice Hall, 1970.

[17] Ramsey FP. `Facts and Propositions' -- In: The Foundations of Mathematics. L., 1931.

[18] Tarski A. The Semantic Conception of Truth and the Foundations of Semantics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 1944; 4(3): 341--375.

[19] Wittgenstein L. Philosophical investigations, Translated by GEM Anscombe. Basil Blackwell, 1958, 250 p.

[20] Wright von GH. Philosophical Papers of Georg Henrik von Wright. Vol. II: Philosophical Logic. Cornell University Press, Ithaka, New York, 1983.

Ðàçìåùåíî íà Allbest.ru

...

Ïîäîáíûå äîêóìåíòû

  • What is meant by Kant’s "Copernican Revolution"? What is the "Transcendental Aesthetic" about? Explain what Kant means by intuition, pure intuition, empirical intuition; concept, pure concept, empirical concept; transcendent.

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [23,0 K], äîáàâëåí 09.04.2007

  • Fr. Nietzsche as German thinker who lived in the second half of the Nineteenth Century. The essence of the concept of "nihilism". Peculiarities of the philosophy of Socrates. Familiarity with Nietzsche. Analysis of drama "Conscience as Fatality".

    äîêëàä [15,3 K], äîáàâëåí 09.03.2013

  • Causes and corresponding types of deflation. Money supply side deflation. Credit deflation, Scarcity of official money. Alternative causes and effects. The Austrian and keynesian school of economics. Historical examples: deflation in Ireland, Japan, USA.

    ðåôåðàò [45,6 K], äîáàâëåí 13.12.2010

  • A proverb as a simple and concrete saying popularly known and repeated, which expresses a truth, based on common sense or the practical experience of humanity. Confucius as the most famous creator of proverbs. Grammatical structures of proverbs.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [895,6 K], äîáàâëåí 05.04.2013

  • Match the right words to form expressions from the first two paragraphs of the article. Matching the expressions to the equivalent expressions. Answering are the statements true or false or is it impossible to say, given the information in the article.

    êîíòðîëüíàÿ ðàáîòà [32,9 K], äîáàâëåí 16.05.2010

  • Reading the article. Matching the expressions from the first two paragraphs of this article. Answer if following statements true or false or is it impossible to say, are given the information in the article. Find adjectives to complete some definitions.

    êîíòðîëüíàÿ ðàáîòà [33,0 K], äîáàâëåí 29.04.2010

  • The study of political discourse. Political discourse: representation and transformation. Syntax, translation, and truth. Modern rhetorical studies. Aspects of a communication science, historical building, the social theory and political science.

    ëåêöèÿ [35,9 K], äîáàâëåí 18.05.2011

  • St. Patrick, the patron saint of Ireland, is one of Christianity's most widely known figures. Taken Prisoner By Irish Raiders. No Irish Need Apply. Wearing of the Green Goes Global. Other Superstitions. The Truth about Saint Patrick. Sayings and Toasts.

    ðåôåðàò [21,6 K], äîáàâëåí 04.05.2009

  • Definition of adverb, its importance as part of the language, different classifications of famous linguists, such as: classification of adverbs according to their meaning, form, function in a sentence. Considered false adverbs and their features.

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [41,4 K], äîáàâëåí 19.03.2015

  • The causes and effects of the recent global financial crisis. Liquidity trap in Japan. Debt deflation theory. The financial fragility hypothesis. The principles of functioning of the financial system. Search for new approaches to solving debt crises.

    ðåôåðàò [175,9 K], äîáàâëåí 02.09.2014

  • Modes and types of interpreting and also lexical aspects of interpreting. Handling context-free and context-bound words. Handling equivalent-lacking words and translators false friends. Translation of cultures and political terms. Translation of verbs.

    äèïëîìíàÿ ðàáîòà [84,6 K], äîáàâëåí 22.03.2012

  • English traditions, known for the whole world. Main traditions of the United Kingdom of Great Britain. Traditional dividing of London by three parts: the West End, the East end, and the City. Politeness is a characteristic feature of Englishmen.

    ðåôåðàò [22,0 K], äîáàâëåí 23.04.2011

  • The concept and the main causes of atherosclerosis, primary symptom. The mechanisms of atherosclerosis, main causes The symptoms and consequences, prevention. Atherosclerosis treatments. Basic approaches to diagnosis and treatment of this disease.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [813,1 K], äîáàâëåí 21.11.2013

  • The lexical problems of literary translation from English on the Russian language. The choice of the word being on the material sense a full synonym to corresponding word of modern national language and distinguished from last only by lexical painting.

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [29,0 K], äîáàâëåí 24.04.2012

  • A specific feature of services. The main form of supply of services abroad. A need for international regulation of trade in services. Operations on foreign tourism. International tourism as a form of foreign economic activity. World Tourism Organization.

    ðåôåðàò [1,2 M], äîáàâëåí 30.09.2014

  • The political regime: concept, signs, main approaches to the study. The social conditionality and functions of the political system in society. Characteristic of authoritarian, totalitarian, democratic regimes. Features of the political regime in Ukraine.

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [30,7 K], äîáàâëåí 08.10.2012

  • Structure (composition) of advertisements is determined by their purpose and tasks referred to. A very common feature of any advertisement is the advertising claims which possesses certain peculiarities and is of great interest to a translator.

    ðåôåðàò [12,4 K], äîáàâëåí 02.10.2009

  • The geographical position of Australia, footprint, capital. The topography and climate of the continent, mined minerals, the flora and fauna. The most important industries. Products for export. A significant feature of modern Australian society.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [1,7 M], äîáàâëåí 28.05.2015

  • Characteristic features of Slang. Feature Articles: Magical, Ritual, Language and Trench Slang of the Western front. Background of Cockney English. Slang Lexicographers. The Bloomsbury Dictionary Of Contemporary slang. Slang at the Millennium.

    êóðñîâàÿ ðàáîòà [69,2 K], äîáàâëåí 21.01.2008

  • New York is the largest city in the U.S. History of formation of city. The Big Apple is the second name in New York. The city's population. The Fifth Avenue is a street in downtown Manhattan. Staten Island Ferry. A feature of the New York subway.

    ïðåçåíòàöèÿ [3,6 M], äîáàâëåí 01.03.2012

Ðàáîòû â àðõèâàõ êðàñèâî îôîðìëåíû ñîãëàñíî òðåáîâàíèÿì ÂÓÇîâ è ñîäåðæàò ðèñóíêè, äèàãðàììû, ôîðìóëû è ò.ä.
PPT, PPTX è PDF-ôàéëû ïðåäñòàâëåíû òîëüêî â àðõèâàõ.
Ðåêîìåíäóåì ñêà÷àòü ðàáîòó.