Imagination in action: the case of historical epistemology

The value of imagination in science, the role that imagination plays in interdisciplinary scientific communication. A specific type of communication in which science is the subject of research. Inharmonious interaction between different disciplines.

Рубрика Философия
Вид статья
Язык английский
Дата добавления 14.11.2021
Размер файла 31,4 K

Отправить свою хорошую работу в базу знаний просто. Используйте форму, расположенную ниже

Студенты, аспиранты, молодые ученые, использующие базу знаний в своей учебе и работе, будут вам очень благодарны.

Размещено на http://www.allbest.ru/

Imagination in action: the case of historical epistemology

Yulia V. Shaposhnikova -

PhD in Philosophy, associate professor. Saint Petersburg State University

Lada V. Shipovalova -

DSc in Philosophy, professor. Saint Petersburg State University

Abstract

The intention of this article is to study the role of imagination in science. We are going to examine the communicative role that imagination plays in interdisciplinary scientific interaction. We are referring to that specific kind of interaction in which science is the object of research that is to a complicated situation in the contemporary science studies. We posit that the interaction between different disciplines engaged in the study of science is far from being concordant. This is especially true of the history and philosophy of science. Currently, the situation is such that, on the one hand, the philosophical reference to the historical research of science has proved being constructive in nature. On the other hand, historians remain mostly indifferent to the philosophy of science, seeking no methodological guidance from philosophers. Revealing the reasons for such an asymmetry of interests, and, as a consequence, the failure of the constructive interaction of history and philosophy of science, we analyze one hypothesis which directly refers to the work of imagination in the Kantian sense. Next, we determine that Kant's appeal to imagination opens the way for another interpretation of both the work of imagination and, as a result, the interaction of history and philosophy of science. We demonstrate why the analysis of the role of image, associated primarily with art, becomes relevant in modern research of science. Additionally, we turn to imagination, not just as a transcendental condition of knowledge but as an effective tool to organize specific research practices of interdisciplinary interaction. Therefore, an important component of our research is an appeal to a "successful" example of the synthesis of historical and philosophical research of science, which is the contemporary historical epistemology, in which one can see imagination in action.

Keywords: imagination, Kant, interdisciplinary communication, history and philosophy of science, historical epistemology

ВООБРАЖЕНИЕ В ДЕЙСТВИИ: СЛУЧАЙ ИСТОРИЧЕСКОЙ ЭПИСТЕМОЛОГИИ

Шапошникова Юлия

Владимировна - кандидат философских наук, доцент. Санкт-Петербургский государственный университет

Шиповалова Лада Владимировна - доктор философских наук, профессор Санкт-Петербургский государственный университет

Аннотация

Данная статья рассматривает значение воображения в науке, а именно роль, которую воображение играет в междисциплинарной научной коммуникации. При этом в фокусе внимания оказывается тот специфический вид коммуникации, в котором наука выступает предметом исследования. В статье утверждается, что взаимодействие между различными дисциплинами, вовлекающимися в исследование науки, не является гармоничным, и особенно это следует признать относительно взаимодействия истории и философии науки. Ситуация такова, что хотя, с одной стороны, философские апелляции к историческим исследованиям науки уже продемонстрировали свою конструктивность, с другой стороны, историки науки по преимуществу остаются индифферентными по отношению к философии науки, не обращаясь к ней за методологическим руководством. Обнаруживая причины такой асимметрии интересов и, как следствие, провал конструктивного взаимодействия истории и философии науки, в статье анализируется одна гипотеза, которая напрямую отсылает к работе воображения в смысле, который придает ей И. Кант в "Критике чистого разума". Далее демонстрируется, что кантовская интерпретация воображения, присутствующая в "Критике способности суждения", может служить основанием для иного, конструктивного взаимодействия истории и философии науки. Также обосновывается, почему анализ работы воображения, связываемого по преимуществу с искусством, оказывается уместным в современных исследованиях науки, где воображение служит не столько трансцендентальным условием познания, сколько эффективным средством организации практик междисциплинарной научной коммуникации. Важным заключительным элементом статьи является апелляция к "успешному" примеру синтеза исторических и философских исследований науки в современной исторической эпистемологии, демонстрирующему воображение в действии.

Ключевые слова: воображение, Кант, междисциплинарная коммуникация, история и философия науки, историческая эпистемология

Introduction

An ability of the mind to create images not directly corresponding to real and sensible objects but independent of them is called imagination. Being a spontaneous ability, imagination works on the border of real and phantasmagoric. The nature of it is rather complex and, consequently, allows a wide range of approaches and interpretations. Traditionally, imagination is considered a feature of art - poetic, illustrative, and dynamic. However, its role in science is also meaningful and yet requires clarification.

What has alienated scientists from employing imagination in all times and made them refrain from including imagination in a range of scientific methods is the fact that quite independent of any factual reality, of things one can point at, imagination opens the path to phantasma, to "empty images", to seeming but not being. Conversely, the rigor and accuracy required for scientific justification from the very birth of modern science has required precision and knowing, but not imagining. imagination science communication

Yet, the free emergence and further play of images inherent in the ability to imagine represents a source of novelty and originality, crucial to any creativity, including scientific [Thagard & Stewart, 2011; Nersessian, 2009]. Imagination is, thus, in some sense going beyond the boundaries of the perceived to the realm of the possible, integral to any scientific discovery. Apart from being a source of novelty, imagination fills gaps in perception and thus restores a partially completed scientific world picture to the whole. In this regard, Albert Einstein insisted that "Imagination is more important than knowledge. For knowledge is limited to all we now know and understand, while imagination embraces the entire world, and all there ever will be to know and understand" [Einstein, 1929]. Imagination forms a basis for thought experiments widely used in scientific theorizing. Be it classical science or contemporary studies, researchers of all times have used imagination as a mind-expanding tool. The thought experiments of Galileo, clarifying qualities of physical bodies and gravity; of Descartes concerning the duality and nature of consciousness and the contemporary thought models of philosophers of Mind (zombies, closed rooms, etc.) are just a few examples. However, while it is irrefutable that imagination plays an integral role in thought experimenting, debates continue on whether imagination can be applied only in the context of discovery [Spaulding, 2016] or can also be expanded to the context of justification [Gendler, 2000]. Some scholars, conversely, consider imagination as a truly epistemic tool for it helps to justify our contingent beliefs about the world, although not in all cases [Kind, 2018].

Focusing on social aspects of science, contemporary scholars also emphasize the communicative perspective of imagination, since imagining allows an understanding of others, their specific modes of thinking, and, thus, the causes of their actions [Markman et al., 2009].

Imagination plays various roles in the scientific research.1 But it can also be fundamentally excluded from it, being a condition of artistic practices, primarily related to creativity. The history of the relation between science and art provides a vivid illustration of how ambiguous is the role of imagination.Different epistemic roles of imagination are discussed in a collection of papers: [Kind & Kung, 2016]. On the history of the attitude to imagination in science see: [Daston, 1998]. As L. Daston shows in her article, relations between imagination and science have undergone numerous changes in human history. Daston demonstrates that depending on the interpretation of how knowledge is acquired imagination either receives its role in cognition or is being eliminated as subjective and irrelevant to reality. In this research, we are going to accentuate the communicative role which imagination plays in the interdisciplinary scientific interaction. We will not only refer to the interaction of sciences but to that specific kind of interaction, in which science is the object of research, i.e. to a complicated situation in the contemporary science studies. What is this complexity?

It is obvious that the phenomenon of science, like any other equally significant social phenomenon, is a "divided territory" and the subject of various research approaches: sociological, historical, psychological, epistemological, cultural, philosophical [Hendry, 2016, p. 40]. However, the integration of disciplines studying science and their constructive interaction, which aims at both the completeness of the presented material concerning science, and the consistency of the generalization of this material, is as desirable as it is virtually unattainable [Arabatzis, Howard, 2015]. Being limited by the need for disciplinary identification, which means drawing boundaries and establishing significant differences between each other, this interaction can be defined as rather a conflict of identities that claim a preferential cognitive right in the "field of science", instead of allowing cooperation [Riesch, 2014]. What can be a condition for the emergence of, if not sustainable collaboration, but at least local "trading zones" between different disciplines that study science?On the concept of "trading zones" and its application to the situations of interdisciplinary interaction see: [Kasavin, 2017]. The question can be put more radically - what can be a condition for such interaction between disciplines studying science, which will take into account the "voice" of the studied science itself? We will consider the answers to these questions, referring to one particular interaction in the research of science - the modern relationship between history and philosophy of science.

It should be emphasized that this interaction is far from being a harmonious union, despite a current rather concordant co-presence of history and philosophy of science in the institutional and research realms, as well as in the educational sphere. A sharp distinction between the approaches of history and philosophy of science can be described by means of the oppositions of historicism and essentialism in the basic settings, descriptivism and normativity in the methodology, variability and invariance with respect to the interpretation of the subject of study [Kuukkanen, 2016]. An attempt to remove the opposition of these approaches in the spirit of Kant's resolution of antinomies - a demonstration that these positions are related to different objects, the first to the science itself as the subject of research, and the second to the scientific objects - helps to clarify the differences, but only highlights the impossibility of interaction of disciplines. Currently, the situation is such that, on the one hand, the philosophical reference to the historical research of science has proved its constructiveness.

On the other hand, historians remain mostly indifferent to the philosophy of science, having no tendency to philosophical conceptualizations and seeking for no methodological guidance from philosophers.

Revealing the reasons for such asymmetry of interests, and, as a consequence, the failure of the constructive interaction of history and philosophy of science, we will analyze one hypothesis, which explains the aforementioned reasons, and which directly refers to the work of imagination in the Kantian sense. Next, we will find that Kant's appeal to imagination opens the way for another interpretation of both the work of imagination and, consequently, the interaction of history and philosophy of science. Then, we will turn to imagination, not just as a transcendental condition of knowledge, but as an ability to organize specific research practices of interdisciplinary interaction. Therefore, an important component of our research will be an appeal in the last part of the article to the "successful" example of the synthesis of historical and philosophical research of science, which is the contemporary Historical Epistemology, in which one can observe imagination in action.On the contemporary historical epistemology, its methodological certainty and topical problems see: [Feest & Sturm, 2011].

Imagination as a Transcendental Condition for the Failure of Interdisciplinary Synthesis of Science Studies

The failure of the history and philosophy of science as a mutual project, in which participants recognize the equality of interests of each other, is explained and partly constituted by the well-known formula of Imre Lakatos that "the Philosophy of science without the History of science is empty; the History of science without the Philosophy of science is blind" [Riesch, 2014]. This formula justifies the possibility of a rational reconstruction of the history of science by the normative methodology of the history of science [Lakatos, 1981, p. 107]. Lakatos's statement reflects Kant's interpretation of the relationship between the two necessary cognitive faculties - passive sensibility and spontaneity of understanding - as well as of their necessary connection: "Without sensibility no object would be given to us, and without understanding none would be thought. Thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind. It is thus just as necessary to make the mind's concepts sensible (i.e., to add an object to them in intuition) as it is to make its intuitions understandable (i.e., to bring them under concepts)" [Kant, 1998, B 75-76]. What makes possible the desired connection between sensibility and understanding is the transcendental synthesis of imagination, which comes into play when the question of cognition of the object arises, and not just of thinking about. Due to the faculty of imagination "the categories, as mere forms of thought, acquire objective reality, i.e., application to objects that can be given to us in intuition" [Kant, 1998, B 151]. It is here that Kant defines imagination as "the faculty for representing an object even without its presence in intuition" [ibid.], which corresponds to the common interpretation of imagination presented above. Kant explains the possibility of being a mediator by employing both sensibility representing an object in intuition, and spontaneity carrying out the synthesis of intuitions. In this sense, imagination turns out to be both defining (active) and defined (passive) ability. But, despite the fact that Kant highlights an equal need for both of these abilities for the process of cognition [ibid., B 76], the passivity or receptivity of sensibility as opposed to the free spontaneity of reason in the Critique of Pure Reason has a lower status, and the mediating activity of imagination is subject to the rules of understanding.G. Deleuze, who interprets Kant's teaching of faculties, emphasizes one meaning of the word faculty: to exist as a source of representations. At the same time, according to Deleuze, sensibility, unlike imagination, understanding and reason, should not be considered as such a source, because, in this term (representation), the most meaningful is reproduction, that is, an active action applied to what has already been given, initially to the resulting variety. Sensibility in this sense turns out to be passive [Deleuze, 1983, p. 7-9]. The examination of the syntheses that the imagination carries out, especially those related to the first edition of the Critique of Pure Reason, lies beyond the scope of our study. Here, we only focus on the "productive imagination" according to the definition given earlier.

Thus, the Kant-Lakatos statement referring to the work of imagination, legitimizes such a way of interaction between the two disciplines studying science which simultaneously explains its failure. Historians provide content for the spontaneity of understanding, while the active conceptual synthesis applied to historical material entirely belongs to the activity of the philosopher. Such a hierarchical attitude puts the historian in a subordinate position to the philosopher, who is responsible both for the formulation of normative rules of how science should be interpreted, and for their application to a specific material of the development of science, and, thus, creates a problem of interdisciplinary interaction. The very development of science is considered a process subject to philosophical evaluation. It is unlikely that this situation of original inequality can save Lakatos's desire to show "how the historiography of science should learn from the philosophy of science and vice versa" [Lakatos, 1981, p. 107].

Reconstruction of the history of science, following in general terms the methodological requirements of Lakatos, is based on the normative meta-language of philosophy. It relies on a certain understanding of the conditions for the development of scientific knowledge, knowing the differences in two contexts - of discovery and of justification, considering the content of concepts of truth and lies, and it rests on certain basic values as the criteria of science, etc. Rational reconstruction is engaged in the application of these "a priori" installations to the processes of development of scientific knowledge being a conductor of philosophical selection and trial over the real scientific practices. Philosophy of science here "legislates", providing "accord" to the internal elements of the discipline (History and Philosophy of science), similar to how in the field of cognitive interest in Kant's the Critique of Pure Reason, understanding legislates the accord of cognitive faculties, subduing the faculty of imagi - nation [Deleuze, 1984, p. 68]. This legislation is due to the fact that it is understanding and its concepts that provide a claim to the universality of knowledge (its objective validity), as well as by means of imagination the subordination of the object to the subjectivity of the knower (objective reality).P. Guyer defines objective reality as a characteristic of representations that indicates that they have an actual object. Objective validity determines the representations in their universal application to the objects of the corresponding class. [Guyer, 2006, p. 376]. Recognition or neglect of this distinction depends on the interpretation of the role of productive imagination - whether it is responsible for the figurative synthesis or it is subject to intellectual synthesis of understanding. Is a different situation possible where the disciplines researching science would interact as equals? Or, approaching the question transcendentally, can we assume as a condition for such an interaction a different proportion of cognitive abilities, which would correlate their internal relationship with their "mutual quickening" [Kant, 1987, p. 88]?

Imagination as a Transcendental Condition for The Constructive Interdisciplinary Synthesis of Science Studies

The required proportion is also related to the role that imagination can play. The role of imagination, for Kant, is not limited to schematism, as described in the Critique of Pure Reason. In the Critique of Judgment, Kant contends that imagination also schematizes without any concept and, thus, he speaks of its freedom. [ibid., p. 151]. The second of Kant's interpretations of imagination, where entering into "a free play" with understanding, defines another opportunity for interaction between cognitive faculties where there is no limiting concept of their actions [ibid., p. 62]. If we continue to follow Lakatos's analogy, this second role of imagination draws our attention to the possibility of a free and equal interaction of the history and philosophy of science, which requires no appeal to the normative methodological meta-language of philosophy, and which would determine the meaning of basic scientific con cepts in advance, as well as explain the logic of the development of scientific knowledge.

It can be shown that the faculty of imagination, according to Kant, in its free attitude to understanding - but in agreement with it, can determine conditions of knowledge, in particular, being a condition for the realization of the reflective judgment. As long as the cognitive activity of science claims universality (objectivity), the condition for the veracity of this claim is "the universal communicability" of knowledge or "the sensus communis" as a result of the coordinated work of cognitive faculties. In turn, this accord is possible only if one of the faculties, for example, understanding, legislates. In this case, which Kant describes in the Critique of Pure Reason, the a priori rules of understanding in their universality and necessity guarantee the universality of knowledge [Deleuze, 1984, p. 23]. However, the problem is that the subordination of other abilities to understanding (or reason, in the case of the Critique of Practical Reason) is only possible if it is based upon the free accord of faculties. It is the freedom of imagination that serves this free accord. Why is it so?

Clarifying the "structure" of common human understanding in the Critique of Judgment, Kant defines three different functions of cognitive faculties and their maxims [Kant, 1987, p. 161]. Unprejudiced thinking as a maxim of understanding involves liberation from prejudice and responsibility for its own knowledge; broadened thinking as a maxim of judgment involves the ability to think from another's perspective, or reflection; consistent thinking as a maxim of reason involves establishing consent with oneself or the coordination of the first and the second. It is easy to understand why the reflective judgment cannot legislate. It is because the desired "universal standpoint", which could become the basis for power, is never given, but it can emerge in the practice of " transferring himself to the standpoint of others" [ibid.], including the yet unknown. In other words, an a priori condition of the judgment legislation that could be attributed to others, does not exist, because otherwise others would not be others. Conversely, the claim to the universality of the reflective judgment is realized by the fact that "we compare our judgments not so much with the actual ones, but rather with what the decision of others is possible, and [thus] put ourselves in the place of everyone else, simply abstracting from the limitations that [may] happen to attach to our own judgments" [ibid., p. 160]. At the heart of the reflection procedure here lies precisely the work of the productive imagination, which is "the faculty for representing an object even without its presence in intuition" [ibid, p. 256], that is, the facility to work on the image of an object, taking into account even those points of perception that have not yet been realized. It is this work that explains how filling gaps in perception is possible when creating an image of an object in the scientific cognition [Downie, 2001].

Freedom of the imagination correlates not with the concept of understanding, which in some circumstances may be absent, but with the understanding itself, that is, with its faculty to provide concepts. Thus, the free play of cognitive faculties takes into account the requirement of the general basis of knowledge (its universal communicability), and the need to work on it, but this basis remains a priori uncertain [Kant, 1997, p. 151]. And this uncertainty can be attributed to a recognizable object. In fact, Kant justifies an introduction of the reflective judgment by the presence of "such diverse forms of nature, so many modifications <...> of the universal transcendental concepts of nature which are left undetermined" by the laws of pure understanding" [ibid., p. 19]. Therefore, cognizant of the work of imagination, which organizes the free accord of faculties, we can expect from it the liberation of an object from the power of the subject. Continuing to follow Lakatos's analogy, we can say that imagination in its second role not only provides a condition for free and equal interaction between history and philosophy in the research of the phenomenon of science, but also, freed from any normative concept, gives "voice" to the cognizable object.

Opening of a Possibility for the Work of Imagination in Science and Epistemology

Before presenting evidence of the fact that the equal interaction of history and philosophy of science is not only possible but also actual, we will ask a question: to what extent is such a re-reading of Kant is legitimate? Is applying the concept of the free play of faculties to the context of scientific research acceptable? Should we not leave this concept solely to artistic creativity, and relegate scientific activity to the syntheses carried out according to the legislation of understanding? At least one argument states that such an interpretation is valid. The relationship between free imagination "schematizing without any concepts" and the scientific cognition came into being in a certain historical period and was quite definite to Kant. Perhaps, by now this relationship has changed and the antipathy between imagination and science has passed away?We refer to the essential for contemporary historical epistemology attitude to basic scientific concepts, the epistemological and ontological status of which is not always appropriate to consider as eternal and unchangeable [Daston, 2000]. If this is the case, then the relationship between science and artistic creation, since the ability of imagination belongs primarily to the latter, may also change. Perhaps it was not so unambiguous in the past. On the intersection of scientific research practices and artistic activities, in history in particular, see: [Baigrie, 1996; Jones & Galison, 1998].

What can testify to the justification of free imagination in science at present? This justification can be associated with the actualization of a certain image of science, involving criticism of the legislative power of understanding or a critical attitude to science as a system of theoretical representations. This criticism is seen in a number of significant epistemological works of the late 20th century.Identification of reasons for this tendency deserves a separate study. Here we can only note that this tendency partly continues the line of empiricism in positivist studies of science but is amplified by the critical attitude to theoretical scientific representations on the part of social sciences [Marcus & Fisher, 1986], as well as by the general postmodern intellectual situation known for its suspicion towards any universalism. R. Rorty, arguing about scientific values, criticizes the ambition of science to retain objectivity, understood in a representative way [Rorty, 1991]. J. Hacking, referring to the problem of realism in science, prefers realism of scientific objects associated with the direct experimental interaction with reality to the realism of scientific theories, which seems problematic to him [Hacking, 1983]. N. Cartwright, clarifying the status of models in science, shows that theoretical regularities do not describe regularities existing in nature, that in science "the phenomenological laws are indeed true of the objects in reality - or might be; but the fundamental laws are true only of objects in the model" [Cartwright, 1983, p. 4]. The methodology of science begins to develop the so-called non-representative approaches that emphasize an empirical component of the research [Vanini, 2015; Trift, 2007]. The criticism of science as a theoretical activity emphasizes a practical side of science, related to empirical objects and their images, giving way to imaginative schematizing without a concept. Thus, a new historical approach to the study of science emerges. Being no subject to concepts assigned by philosophy, it creates and reassembles them anew.

This new approach is associated not only and not so much with the historization of the theory of scientific knowledge, bequeathed by representatives of previous epistemological traditions, for example, French epistemology [Lecourt, 1975] or Marxist tradition [Wartofsky, 1987], but with the epistemologization of the history of science. The latter distinguishes the contemporary history of science. Modern historical epistemology takes upon itself the organization of a meeting of two equal research interests [Rheinberger, 2012, p. 111]. Works in this field do not simply describe individual scientific events or long-term processes, but refer to the genesis of contemporary epistemological problems as to a source, in which their solution can be found [Hacking, 2002, p. 24].Here we can remember one quite illustrative example of the study of "science archive" by L. Daston [Daston, 2012]. In her work, Daston describes the obligatory presence in "sciences of nature" the historical memory and the attention to individual facts of the past, traditionally characteristic to "sciences of culture". Noteworthy, at the beginning of her study, she reveals its purpose - to demonstrate rather rigorous limitations set by a quite problematic contemporary approach, which insists on the firmness of interdisciplinary differences between humanities and natural science. Here philosophy and history of science as disciplinary research strategies intersect, learning from each other and from science itself.

Let us examine two examples which demonstrate the actual work of free imagination as a synthesis of history and philosophy of science. It is crucial that this work rejects an a priori acceptance of a concept, which in some sense defines science as a subject of research. In addition, science itself is understood here as a set of research practices, which includes operating with an object never fully defined. In these examples, it is assumed that the historical analysis of scientific practices allows the forming of a new image of science, and, in this formation, universal communicability is in effect, taking into account variable representations of this image. Formally, this image of science includes two elements - objectivity as a basic scientific value, and scientific object. Substantially these characteristics are the subject of "reassembling", which imagination performs.

Imagination in Historical Epistemology - Two Cases of Constructive Interdisciplinary Communication

The first case concerns the study of the concept of "epistemic virtue", that is, the regulatory ideal of scientific activity, which in the traditional interpretation is associated with objectivity. D. Daston and P. Galison, in their fundamental work Objectivity, question this concept [Daston & Galison, 2007]. The authors prove that the identification of science and objectivity and also the use of objectivity as an absolute characteristic of science are not correct either historically or conceptually. They assert that objectivity is not the only and everlasting epistemic virtue, but that it arose at a certain time (not earlier than the first half of the 19 th century), and there are reasons for its occurrence and the enhancement of its power. The text combines two levels of reassembly - of the concept of epistemic virtue as such, which is diverse, and of the concept of objectivity, which is considered an epistemic virtue along with such concepts as "truth to nature" and "trained judgment", but which is also quite ambiguous since it orients different scientific practices in various ways.

The methodological approach used in this text is important to us. At the core of this approach lies the rejection of the dogmatism of a certain sense of a concept, which leads to a shift of focus from the readymade concept to concrete practices (in the case Objectivity to the practice of making scientific atlases). As a result of the analysis of practices, a new assembly of the concept emerges. "If actions are substituted for concepts and practices for meanings, the focus on the nebulous notions of objectivity sharpens" [ibid., p. 52]. That is, the construction of a concept occurs, not the application of a ready-made concept to a scientific experience. Such a construction, "a non-teleological history of scientific objectivity", can only have the most formally defined purpose - to show how under one word converges different kinds of practices [Daston & Galison, 2007, p. 29]. A meaningful definition of objectivity - objectivity as overcoming of subjectivity - should be the result of this process. Noteworthy is the fact that in this concept, defined only formally, there is a place for other, not yet considered meanings of objectivity, and each of them is determined by which kind of subjectivity hinders scientific cognition in each particular case. In other words, the methodological approach of historical epistemology, implemented in this text, corresponds to the criticism of theoretical representations, and opens up opportunities for the work of free imagination, that is the schematization without any readymade concept. It is interesting that the concept of objectivity is also defined by the authors in a non-representative way: "Objectivity is blind sight, seeing without inference, interpretations, or intelligence" [ibid., p. 17].

The reassembly of the concept of objectivity in this text can be considered not only in the context of criticism of scientific representations, but also as an illustrative example of a combination of historical analysis and philosophical problem solving, in the question of the basic guidelines of scientific activity. "History alone", state L. Daston and P. Galison, "cannot make the choice, any more than one can make the choice among competing moral virtues. But it can show that the choice exists and what hinges on it" [ibid., p. 42]. Let us pay attention to the essential difference between the approach of historical epistemology and the rational reconstruction of the history of science. In the second approach, history, according to I. Lakatos, is subject to the normative methodology of the philosophy of science. Normativity means an opportunity to explain the choice made between competing theories, that is, to make an "appraisal of the solutions already there" [Lakatos, 1981, p. 108]. In the first approach, history shows the contingency of each specific scientific solution; its actual variations and possible alternatives. In addition, historical research, being equally active in the disciplinary synthesis, motivates philosophizing by showing alternatives, "turning an apparent axiom - things could never have been otherwise than we known them - into a matter for reasoned argument" [ibid., p. 376]. In this case, we begin to understand not only why scientists put objectivity in the foreground as an ideal and what problems this choice involves, but also what alternatives, not contrary to the standards of science, this choice allows.

Worth mentioning is the special attention that historical epistemolo- gists pay to science and its "voice", which is not found in the epistemological reflections of scientists or hidden in their theoretical texts in the form of adherence to certain themata (G. Holton). This "voice" reveals itself clearly, not in scientific concepts but in images - diagrams, drawings, photographs taken with the help of complex devices. The transformations of these images (intuitions) demonstrate the work of scientific imagination, which remains hidden from the normative methodology of a philosopher of science.

Another case of translating self-evident axioms into objects of reasoned discussion is advanced by H.-J. Rheinberger in his work On the History of Epistemic Things, where he focuses on the concept of a scientific object [Rheinberger, 1997]. Traditional epistemology assumes invariance as an essential feature of scientific objects. It is this feature that determines the reproducibility of the experiment and characterizes the objectivity of an object [Nozick, 1998], as long as the analysis is limited to the "context of justification", while the "context of discovery" is considered insignificant. H.-J. Rheinberger describes one history - or even a biography - of such scientific objects as cytoplasmic particles, which have played a major role in emergence, between 1935 and 1965, of what is in molecular biology now known as RNA - Ribonucleic acid. He not only shifts the focus to the "context of discovery", to the "coming into being of scientific object"; he suggests we should problematize invariance as an essential quality of scientific objects instead of working within a framework of normative conceptual dichotomy of discovery and justification, and pay attention to scientific practices as such, which always include two kinds of objects.

The first is the "epistemic thing". Rheinberger uses this term to refer to a scientific object, participating in the event of "coming into being", that is in the process of inclusion into the stable scientific objecticity, which has obtained the naming and strictly defined characteristics. Cytoplasmic particles as epistemic things initially have fallen into the focus of interest of various sciences (cancer research, biochemistry, molecular biology, cytomorphology, etc.). They have been studied with a help of various technical means (differential centrifugation with modification of its conditions, "amino acid tracing", electron microscopy, etc.), had different localizations and even different names (mitochondria, microsome, "ribonucleoprotein" particles, ribosomes). Only one quality of these particles was considered indisputable by scientists - their participation in the protein synthesis. The epistemic things as objects of research appear fundamentally uncertain and vague and "this vagueness is inevitable because, paradoxically, epistemic things embody what one does not yet know" [Rheinberger, 1997, p. 28]. In the case of epistemic things, there is no a priori established connection between the concept and the referent. Moreover, no concept regarding them exists altogether. All that can be done is to give a list of constitutive practices, which each time redefines the object differently. Scientists must create this concept step by step with the help of imagination schematizing without any concept.

The second kind of objects is the "technical thing". These are the stable objects that provide practices of research, experimental conditions, models, ready-made concepts, instructions, equipment; things that with the help of which an object of study becomes articulated or visible in one sense or another [Rheinberger, 1997, p. 29]. The difference between technical and epistemic things is situational. The fate of the second is to b ecome a stabilized object, to acquire a stable naming, a certain referent, and eventually, to become a technical thing for subsequent scientific practices. In other words, the two types of scientific objects are not on separate stages of scientific research, they constitute no hierarchy of importance but complement each other, and their difference is purely functional. They and their mixtures (hybrids) also form the lab environment and vary as "`materials and methods' (technical things) `results' (half-way hybrids) and`discussions' (epistemic things)" [ibid., p. 30].

Similar to Daston and Galison, Rheinberger uses several levels of reassembling. Firstly, he re-assembles the concept of scientific object and he employs the method of "reading a history of objectivity from material traces" not "reading a history of objectivity from concepts" [ibid., p. 4]. Secondly, he demonstrates how re-assembly of a scientific object occurs in scientific practice. The concept of an epistemic thing, which corresponds to one of numerous functions of scientific research, characterizes, as Rheinberger puts it, "redefinition" occurring in a laboratory. On both levels, a non-representative strategy emerges, the movement "from the bottom up", if, of course, we following the spirit of traditional rationalist epistemology and assemble scientific practices and theoretical representation in a hierarchy. Rheinberger's historical study, as well as Daston's and Galison's work, partakes in the philosophical transformation of the image of science. History, in principle, ceases to be a historian's business alone but, thanks to the discovery of the historicity of scientific objects, becomes an essential part of science itself. What a historian used to call "rearrangement" and "reorientation" defining the object of scientific activity is now part "of the time structure of the innermost differential activity of the system of investigations themselves" [ibid., p. 178].

Thus, we see how interdisciplinary communication works between history and philosophy of science in the historical epistemology. Moreover, this communication allows various studies to interact on equal terms and offers history an active role. Furthermore, science itself participates in this communication; scientific practices uncover all pre-formed images of scientific activity, and enrich scooping from the space of possible alternatives, which historical study provides. The transcendental basis of such communication can form the ability of imagination, schematizing without any given concept. The ability of imagination works on the borderline between the real and the possible and therefore helps to build an image of science, which respects different viewpoints and is open to new transformations.

Список литературы / References

1. Arabatzis, Howard, 2015 - Arabatzis, T., Howard, D. "Introduction: Integrated history and philosophy of science in practice ", Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 2015, vol. 50, pp. 1-3.

2. Baigrie, 1996 - Baigrie, B.S. (ed.). Picturing Knowledge: Historical and Philosophical Problems Concerning the Use of Art in Science. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1996, 414 pp.

3. Cartwright, 1983 - Cartwright, N. How the Laws of Physics Lie. New York: Clarendon Press, 1983, 232 pp.

4. Daston, 1998 - Daston, L. "Fear and Loathing of the Imagination in Science", Daedalus, 1998, vol. 127 (1), pp. 73-95.

5. Daston, 2000 - Daston, L. "The Coming into Being of Scientific Objects", in: L. Daston (ed.). Biographies of Scientific Objects. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 2000, pp. 1-14.

6. Daston, 2012 - Daston, L. "The Sciences of the Archive", Osiris, 2012, vol. 27 (1) Clio Meets Science: The Challenges of History, pp. 156-187.

7. Daston & Galison, 2007 - Daston, L., Galison, P. Objectivity. New York: Zone Books, 2007, 504 pp.

8. Deleuze, 1984 - Deleuze, G. Kants Critical Philosophy. The Doctrine of the Faculties. London: The Athlone Press, 1984, 98 pp.

9. Downie, 2001 - Downie, R. "Science and the Imagination in the Age of Reason", Medical Humanities, 2001, vol. 27(2), pp. 58-63.

10. Einstain, 1929 - "What Life Means to Einstein: An Interview by George Sylvester Viereck", in: The Saturday Evening Post (26 October 1929). [http://www. saturdayeveningpost.com/wp-content/uploads/satevepost/what_life_means_to_einstein. pdf, accessed on 20.06.2019]

11. Feest & Sturm, 2011 - Feest, U., Sturm, T. "What (Good) Is Historical Epistemology?", Erkenntnis, 2011, vol. 75(3), pp. 285-302.

12. Gentler, 2000 - Gendler, T.S. "Thought Experiments Rethought - and Reperceived", Philosophy of Science, 2000, vol. 71(5), pp. 1152-1163.

13. Guyer, 2006 - Guyer, P. Kant. London and New York: Routledge, 2006, 521 pp.

14. Hacking, 1983 - Hacking, I. Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983, 304 pp.

15. Hacking, 2002 - Hacking, I. Historical Ontology. London, Harper University Press, 2002, 288 pp.

16. Hendry, 2016 - Hendry, R.F. "Immanent Philosophy of X", Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 2016, vol. 55, pp. 36-42.

17. Jones & Galison, 1998 - Jones, C.A., & Galison, P. (eds.). Picturing Science, Producing Art. New York, London: Routledge, 1998, 530 pp.

18. Kant, 1987 - Kant, I. Critique of Judgment. Transl. by MS. Pluhar. Indianapolis/ Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, 1987, 576 pp.

19. Kant, 1998 - Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason. Transl. and edited by P. Guyer & A.W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998, 785 pp.

20. Kasavin, 2017 - Kasavin, I.T. "Zony obmena kak predmet sotsial'noy filosofii nauki" [Trading Zones as a Subject-matter of Social Philosophy o Science], Epistemology & philosophy of science, 2017, vol. 51, no. 1, pp. 8-17. (In Russian)

21. Kind, 2018 - Kind, A. "How Imagination Gives Rise to Knowledge in Perceptual Imagination and Perceptual Memory", in: F. Macpherson and F. Dorsch (eds.). Perceptual Imagination and Perceptual memory. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018, pp. 227-246.

22. Kind & Kung, 2016 - Kind, A., Kung, P. (eds.), Knowledge Through Imagination, New York: Oxford University Press, 2016, 272 pp.

23. Kuukkanen, 2016 - Kuukkanen, J.-M. "Historicism and the failure of HPS", Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 2016, vol. 55, pp. 3-11.

24. Lakatos, 1981 - Lakatos, I. "History of Science and its Rational Reconstructions", in: I. Hacking (ed.). Scientific Revolutions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981, pp. 107-127.

25. Lecourt, 1975 - Lecourt, D. Marxism and Epistemology: Bachelard, Canguil- hem, and Foucault. London: NLB, 1975, 223 pp.

26. Marcus & Fischer, 1986 - Marcus, G.E., Fischer, M.M.I. "A Crisis of Representations in the Human Sciences", in: Anthropology as Cultural Critique: An Experimental Moment in the Human Sciences. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1986, pp. 7-16.

27. Markman et al., 2009 - Markman, K.D., Klein, W.M.P, and Suhr, J.A. (eds.). Handbook of Imagination and Mental Simulation, New York: Taylor & Francis, 2009, 496 pp.

28. Nersessian, 2009 - Nersessian, N.J. "Conceptual Change: Creativity, Cognition, and Culture", in: J. Meheus & T. Nickles (eds.). Models of Discovery and Creativity. Dordrecht: Springer, 2009, pp. 127-166.

29. Nozick, 1998 - Nozick, R. "Invariance and Objectivity", Proceeding and Addresses of PA, 1998, vol. 72, pp. 21-48.

30. Rheinberger, 1997 - Rheinberger, H.-J. Towards a History of Epistemic Things. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1997, 338 pp.

31. Rheinberger, 2012 - Rheinberger, H.-J. "A Plea for a Historical Epistemology of Research", Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 2012, vol. 43 (1), pp. 105-111.

32. Riesch, 2014 - Riesch, H. "Philosophy, History and Sociology of Science: Interdisciplinary", Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 2014, vol. 48, pp. 30-37.

33. Rorty, 1991 - Rorty, R. Objectivity, Relativism and Truth. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991, 236 pp.

34. Spaulding, 2016 - Spaulding, S. "Imagination Through Knowledge", in: A. Kind and P. Kung (eds.). Knowledge Through Imagination. New York: Oxford University Press, 2016, pp. 207-226.

35. Thagard & Stewart, 2011 - Thagard, P., Stewart, T. C. The "AHA! Experience: Creativity Through Emergent Binding in Neural Networks", Cognitive Science, 2011, vol. 35, pp. 1-33.

36. Trhrift, 2007 - Thrift, N. Non-Representational Theory: Space, Politics, Affect. London: Routledge, 2007, 336 pp.

37. Vanini, 2015 - Vannini, Ph (ed.). Non-Representational Methodologies. Re-envisioning Research. New York & London: Routledge, 2015, 204 pp.

38. Wartofsky, 1987 - Wartofsky, M. "Epistemology Historised", in: A. Shimony and D. Nails (eds.). Naturalistic Epistemology. Dordrecht: Springer, 1987, pp. 357-374.

Размещено на Allbest.ru

...

Подобные документы

  • There are valid concepts in TE. Some new concepts of NE are not flawless. The new perspectives enrich our contemplative abilities and knowledge. The fully (for all times) satisfactory definitions or foundations are not likely to be proposed.

    курсовая работа [8,5 K], добавлен 29.11.2003

  • The origins of communicative language teaching. Children’s ability to grasp meaning, creative use of limited language resources, capacity for indirect learning, instinct for play and fun. The role of imagination. The instinct for interaction and talk.

    реферат [16,9 K], добавлен 29.12.2011

  • The study of political discourse. Political discourse: representation and transformation. Syntax, translation, and truth. Modern rhetorical studies. Aspects of a communication science, historical building, the social theory and political science.

    лекция [35,9 K], добавлен 18.05.2011

  • The theory and practice of raising the effectiveness of business communication from the linguistic and socio-cultural viewpoint. Characteristics of business communication, analysis of its linguistic features. Specific problems in business interaction.

    курсовая работа [46,5 K], добавлен 16.04.2011

  • Descriptions verbal communication in different cultures. The languages as the particular set of speech norms. Analysis general rules of speaking. Features nonverbal communication in different countries. Concept of communication as complicated process.

    реферат [213,9 K], добавлен 25.04.2012

  • Formation of intercultural business communication, behavior management and communication style in multicultural companies in the internationalization and globalization of business. The study of the branch of the Swedish-Chinese company, based in Shanghai.

    статья [16,2 K], добавлен 20.03.2013

  • Legal linguistics as a branch of linguistic science and academic disciplines. Aspects of language and human interaction. Basic components of legal linguistics. Factors that are relevant in terms of language policy. Problems of linguistic research.

    реферат [17,2 K], добавлен 31.10.2011

  • Role and functions of verbal communication. Epictetus quotes. Example for sympathetic, empathetic listening. Effective verbal communication skills. Parameters of evaluation. Factors correct pronunciation. Use of types of pauses when communicating.

    презентация [53,0 K], добавлен 06.02.2014

  • Theoretical basis of a role plays as a teaching aid. Historic background of game origin. Psychological value of a role plays. The main function and principles of game organization. Gaming technique. Classification of role plays. Advantages of a game.

    курсовая работа [50,7 K], добавлен 26.04.2013

  • Nonverbal methods of dialogue and wrong interpretation of gestures. Historical both a cultural value and universal components of language of a body. Importance of a mimicry in a context of an administrative communication facility and in an everyday life.

    эссе [19,0 K], добавлен 27.04.2011

  • Racism as an instrument of discrimination, as a cultural phenomenon, susceptible to cultural solutions: multicultural education and the promotion of ethnic identities. Addressing cultural inequalities through religion, literature, art and science.

    реферат [33,9 K], добавлен 14.03.2013

  • History of interpreting and establishing of the theory. Translation and interpreting. Sign-language communication between speakers. Modern Western Schools of translation theory. Models and types of interpreting. Simultaneous and machine translation.

    курсовая работа [45,2 K], добавлен 26.01.2011

  • Definition of Metaphor as a Figurative and Expressive Means of Language. Types and the Mechanism of Education of the Metaphor, its difference from comparison. Metaphor role in speech genres, its influence on emotions and imagination of the recipient.

    реферат [43,8 K], добавлен 04.05.2012

  • Communication process is not limited to what we say with words. There are 3 elements of communication: Words (7% of information is communicated though words), Body language (55%) and tone of voice (38%). Thus, 93% of communication is non-verbal.

    топик [4,5 K], добавлен 25.08.2006

  • Modern sources of distributing information. Corpus linguistics, taxonomy of texts. Phonetic styles of the speaker. The peculiarities of popular science text which do not occur in other variations. Differences between academic and popular science text.

    курсовая работа [24,6 K], добавлен 07.02.2013

  • The Communicative Approach. Children’s ability to grasp meaning. Children’s creative use of limited language resources. Children’s instinct for play and fun. Lessons preparation in junior forms. The role of imagination. General steps a lesson preparation.

    курсовая работа [8,2 M], добавлен 02.01.2012

  • Identification of the main features of a subject in the sentence which is based on theoretical and scientific works of Russian, English, American and Romanian authors. Research of a subject and its features in works of the American and English fiction.

    курсовая работа [59,5 K], добавлен 05.05.2011

  • Theory of the communicative language teaching. Principles and features of the communicative approach. Methodological aspects of teaching communication. Typology of communicative language activities. Approbation of technology teaching communication.

    курсовая работа [608,8 K], добавлен 20.10.2014

  • Lines of communication and the properties of the fiber optic link. Selection of the type of optical cable. The choice of construction method, the route for laying fiber-optic. Calculation of the required number of channels. Digital transmission systems.

    дипломная работа [1,8 M], добавлен 09.08.2016

  • Translation is a means of interlingual communication. Translation theory. A brief history of translation. Main types of translation. Characteristic fiatures of oral translation. Problems of oral translation. Note-taking in consecutive translation.

    курсовая работа [678,9 K], добавлен 01.09.2008

Работы в архивах красиво оформлены согласно требованиям ВУЗов и содержат рисунки, диаграммы, формулы и т.д.
PPT, PPTX и PDF-файлы представлены только в архивах.
Рекомендуем скачать работу.