Republicanism and rule-following: subjectivity in the later ludwig wittgenstein's philosophy of language and philip pettit's theory of freedom
Evolution of Wittgenstein’s ideas. Political implications of he’s theory. The critique of liberalism and socialism. Pettit’s solution to rule-following paradox in his political theory. Epistemological argument against domination in political theory.
Рубрика | Философия |
Вид | дипломная работа |
Язык | английский |
Дата добавления | 25.08.2020 |
Размер файла | 49,9 K |
Отправить свою хорошую работу в базу знаний просто. Используйте форму, расположенную ниже
Студенты, аспиранты, молодые ученые, использующие базу знаний в своей учебе и работе, будут вам очень благодарны.
Размещено на http://www.allbest.ru/
Government of the Russian Federation
FEDERAL STATE AUTONOMOUS EDUCATIONAL INSTITUTION FOR HIGHER EDUCATION NATIONAL RESEARCH UNIVERSITY
“HIGHER SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS”
Faculty of Social Sciences
MASTER THESIS
Republicanism and rule-following: subjectivity in the later ludwig wittgenstein's philosophy of language and philip pettit's theory of freedom
Alexander Finiarel
student
Field of Study 41.04.04 Political Science Master's Program “Politics. Economics. Philosophy”
Moscow, 2020
Introduction
Background. Neo-republican theorist Philip Pettit defines republican concept of freedom on the basis of the idea of fitness to be held responsible, accompanied by the idea of ownership and underdetermination. These definitions in their turn are based on a concept of subject, which is very close to Ludwig Wittgenstein's idea of subject. Wittgenstein's concept of subject is most vividly represented in Saul Kripke's investigation of the problem of rule-following and the notion of private language. These conceptions settle subject in the sociolinguistic context that surrounds the subject and in such a way partially externalize the subject.
Pettit studied the problem of rule-following and proposed his own solution to it. I suppose, that he builds his political theory on the basis of this solution. However, in his political works he does not refer neither to Wittgenstein or Kripke nor to his solution. Besides, in politics, he mainly ignores private language argument that is in my opinion important part of rule-following paradox. Unfortunately, there was no any comparative research on neither of these matters.
Problem statement. Pettit does not directly address his investigations of Wittgenstein's ideas of rule-following and private language when drawing his concept of freedom even though in his political theory he follows the same logic that he used resolving the skeptical paradox.
Delimitations of the study. My study is aimed to compare Pettit's ideas on freedom as non-domination and Wittgenstein's research of the problem of rule-following. Therefore, since it is not concerned with the problem of rule-following itself I am not going to investigate the debate on this matter. Neither am I going to discuss the context of Pettit's arguments on rule-following and freedom further than it is necessary for their understanding.
Professional significance. Republican theory of freedom is mostly dominated by historians. Pettit's work gives an interesting perspective on it because he approaches the matter from a more philosophical and psychological perspective. Interpretation of his work from Wittgensteinian perspective could let us to build a bridge between purely political and philosophical aspects of neo-republicanism providing new insights in political sphere.
Literature review
One of the central topics of my research is the discussion of Wittgenstein's idea of subject and the paradox of rule-following investigated by Saul Kripke (1982). Neither of them explicitly defined subject anywhere mostly because Wittgestein's method was based on description of the phenomena he found strange in the language system rather than on creation of a philosophical system. Nevertheless, the relation between the subject and the object or the world is fundamental for his investigations both in his early and in his late periods. His description of this relation undergoes a cardinal change from his early to his late philosophy. This change helps us to understand better his concept of subjectivity. That is why I am going to compare his early Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (Wittgenstein 2011) with his late Philosophical Investigations (Wittgenstein 1986). The most important things to address for this comparison are Wittgenstein's investigation of the problem of solipsism and the problem of private language. The latter is closely connected with the problem of rule-following. This is why I am going to show how Wittgenstein solves this problem in Saul Kripke's interpretation.
This discussion has important implications for political philosophy. Wittgenstein's early work have a lot in common with revolutionary socialist ideas shared by the members of his circle (Russel 2004; Carnap 1932). They aimed to destroy the old world and build a new, better one with the help of reason (Puchner 2005). However, liberals and conservatives often use his later philosophy to criticize socialism (Nyнri.1982; Giddens 1994; Gray 1984; Oakeshott 1991). Such an interpretation is only possible when one tries to avoid pluralism in politics and either leave it to relations between homogenous communities or to the sphere of private (Mouffe 2000). Wittgenstein never tried to escape pluralism and in his later works criticizing his early ideas considered such attempts as meaningless abstractions (Williams 2019). Shoam Shiva (2016) is the only one who tries to connect Pettit's solution to the paradox of rule following ideas with political philosophy. He compares him with Jьrgen Habermas's criticizing him as excessively abstract but he obviously misses the way Pettit overcomes this abstraction through grounding the rules in the everyday use of language.
I want to show how Pettit's own political philosophy being grounded in his epistemology is illuminating in this matter because it shows how different parts of this epistemology work together avoiding depolitization and conservation of the language that is common to communitarianism and conservatism and such modernist political movements as liberalism and socialism. I will look at Pettit's (1990; 1991; 1993) solution to the problem of rule-following and connect it to his political theory. Pettit's solution to the problem of rule-following is very similar to the Kripke's one but has its specifics. He adopts dispositionalist (Johnston 1989; Gendersen 2010), perspective in order to solve the skeptical paradox. In such a way, he restricts both realism and Kripke's purely sociocentric interpretations. Then, Pettit (2001) makes the same move. He is balancing between realism and subjectivism. His approach is based on the idea of fitness to be held responsible that is realistic in the sense that it is an objective property but at the same time it is ethocentric in the sense that the concepts and rules are grasped by the agents in the process of common reasoning and mutual authorization.
The last part is devoted to the discussion of the implications of the connection between Pettit's political philosophy with his ideas on Wittgenstein's later work. I try to show that the relationships between freedom and domination is similar to the ones between rule-following and private language. In order to do that I try to elaborate on Giddens's (1994) and Hayek's (1982) epistemological argument against socialism connecting them to Wittgenstein's private language argument that is mostly ignored by Pettit as an obvious premise for his philosophy. I want to show why an ideal of non-domination is an ideal that the society should reach for developing an epistemological argument against domination. For demonstration of the contradictory nature of domination I want to address Hannah Arendt's (1963; 1968) ideas about totalitarianism as an opposition to Pettit's outline of a free society.
Methodology
Since the main goal of my research is to compare the ways Pettit and Wittgenstein constitute the idea of the subject or the agent, the most obvious choice for methodology is comparative analysis. I am going to contrast Wittgenstein's early and late philosophy for the sake of a better understanding of the reason why he needed the problem of rule-following and the private language argument. Then I am going to give a brief overview of the ways Wittgenstein's ideas influenced political philosophy. After that, I will contrast the way Kripke resolves this problem with the way Pettit does it in order to understand if there is a conceptual difference between them. Finally, I am going to compare the ways Pettit constitutes the concept of the subject when solving the problem of rule-following and when drawing his theory of freedom in order to find out if the later was influenced by the former and if the former could be used as a theoretical basis for the later. On this basis, I want to make an epistemological argument against domination based on private language argument that Pettit usually oversees considering the premise that private language is impossible and that domination is wrong as obvious.
Chapter I. Evolution of Wittgenstein's ideas
Introduction
The relation between the subject and the object (or the world) is one of the core topics in the works of Ludwig Wittgenstein and I dare to say that his account of exactly underwent the most crucial transformation during the evolution of his philosophy this problem. In this chapter, I want to compare the ways Wittgenstein describes this relation in his early and later philosophy in order to understand why this transformation happened and to highlight the solution that according to Saul Kripke he used to overcome for this problem. I suppose that his early solution was endorsing solipsism and equating it to realism but it was only possible due to the objective laws of logic that are behind the structure of the language and it's connection to the world. In his later philosophy, he sees the language as a fluid structure, which is determined not by transcendent rules of logic but by immanent rules established by the subjects. However, a problem arises: since any final set of examples can represent infinite number of rules. Kripke states that Wittgenstein gave a skeptical answer to this problem saying that we should not be bothered with it until the difference in interpretation between the subjects becomes evident. After that, they should simply coordinate their usage of the rules.
The relation between the world and the subject in the early Wittgenstein' philosophy
In Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus Wittgenstein (Витгенштейн 2011) states that the structure of language reflects the structure of the world. For any relation between two objects or things there is a proposition that describes it. The only world that exist is my world, which is also the world of my language.
The world is my world: this is manifest in the fact that the limits of language (of that language which alone I understand) mean the limits of my world. (5.62).
If something cannot be described it cannot exist. The foundation of this connection between language and the world is logic, which sets the limits to the world because nothing that is illogical can be described and therefore does not exist. That is how the language, which I alone - meaning separately from others - understand becomes universal.
The relation between the world and the subject in the early Wittgenstein's philosophy is based on logic, which is a priori and is an essential cognizing tool for the metaphysical subject. All subjects have this attribute in common - if we could speak about multiple subjects in the early Wittgenstein's philosophy at all. Logic and language as well as the world does not depend on the subject. It is, so to speak, a natural thing. That is why the world does not depend on the subject's will even though it is the subject's world.
The Tractatus describes language as a purely descriptive tool. If there is a fact - or at least if this fact is logically possible - than there is a proposition corresponding to it. The propositions depend on nothing else but the facts and logic. The truth of the facts depends only on the truth of the propositions. There is no space for misinterpretation of what other subjects say if they use language correctly.
But what does it mean to use language correctly? Philosophy tries to speak about the transcendental, about the things that does not belong to the world. Logics, math, ethics and aesthetics describe the world and our relation to it. They give a form to accidental facts but they do not belong to the world because they make facts non-accidental. Otherwise, they would be accidental too. “The laws of logic cannot in their turn be subject to laws of logic” (6.123). The propositions of logic do not say anything about the world but only demonstrate the logical structure of other propositions. Logic cannot tell if something exists in the world or not because in this case it should go beyond the limits of the world presupposing that we were excluding certain possibilities.
Nevertheless, logic limits our world. Even though logic is a priory, our experience is not. Logic creates the space of possible states of affairs, the way the world can be described and be non-accidental. “Whatever we can describe at all could be other that it is” (5.634) but it cannot contradict to the laws of logic. Otherwise, it would be unthinkable and lie beyond the limits of our world.
The most part of philosophical questions and propositions are nonsensical for the early Wittgenstein. They “arise from our failure to understand the logic of our language” (4.003). Philosophers try to speak about the unspeakable, about the logic itself. However, “Propositions cannot represent logical form: it is mirrored in them” (4.121). What philosophers should do is “set the limits to what cannot be thought by working outwards what can be thought” (4.114). They should clarify existing propositions instead of creating philosophical ones.
The correct method in philosophy would really be the following: to say nothing except what can be said, i.e. propositions of natural science - i.e. something that has nothing to do with philosophy - and then, whenever someone else wanted to say something metaphysical, to demonstrate to him that he had failed to give a meaning to certain signs in his propositions (6.53).
Wittgenstein imagines here a strange situation when the interlocutor did not give any meaning not to the whole sentence but just to a part of it and this led to a philosophical confusion. The reason for that is that in the Tractatus he speaks about the metaphysical subject. He is alone in the world. Take him out of the world and the world ceases to exist. The early Wittgenstein I dare to say is a solipsist. He even acknowledges that saying that “solipsism, when its implications are followed out strictly, coincides with pure realism” (5.64). His only solution to the problem of solipsism is not to worry about it because the only world I have access to is my own world and anything that is happening in this world is real for me.
How can I be certain that the facts in my world are the same as the facts in the other person's world? - This question the early Wittgenstein forbids us to ask. However, not responding to it we cannot say if our knowledge is certain.
Besides, this theory cuts off an important function of language. The language in The Tractatus is only a descriptive tool. It helps the metaphysical subject to describe the world but it is unclear for whom. In his system, language works like Kantian categories: it only structures the world for the subject. If a proposition does not have a meaning, it does not have a meaning not for someone but in itself. Here the subject describes the world only to oneself.
The relation between the world and the subject in the later Wittgenstein' philosophy
In his later philosophy, Wittgenstein has to address this problem. Consequently, he has to change the whole structure of the relationships between the world and the subject. He begins his main book of the later period - Philosophical Investigations (Wittgenstein 1986) - by criticizing his own old views on language as pure and simple descriptive tool that exists on its own without any context. In order to do that he depicts quite a strange situation:
Now think of the following use of language: I send someone shopping. I give him a slip marked "five red apples". He takes the slip to the shopkeeper, who opens the drawer marked "apples"; then he looks up the word "red" in a table and finds a colour sample opposite it; then he says the series of cardinal numbers - I assume that he knows them by heart - up to the word "five" and for each number he takes an apple of the same colour as the sample out of the drawer. - It is in this and similar ways that one operates with words. - "But how does he know where and how he is to look up the word 'red' and what he is to do with the word 'five'?" - Well, I assume that he acts as I have described. Explanations come to an end somewhere. - But what is the meaning of the word "five"? - No such thing was in question here, only how the word "five" is used. (PI, §1)
Here Wittgenstein tries to apply his early views on language to an ordinary situation that can be encountered in real life and it turns out that this theory does not work. It turns out that his early theory is so abstract that is ”almost tautological”, that it covers only a small part of what language is and how it works, that it is so complicated that Wittgenstein “disclaims any intent of offering a general account of language” (Kripke 1982, 73).
In order to understand how language really works Wittgenstein now addresses the simplest situations of everyday language use and finds out that it is not that strict and logical as he thought before, that language is fluid and its use depends on the situation. Now he describes the structure of language as a game, a set of rules that are to be interpreted differently depending on the context in which they should be applied. Moreover, to one situation can be applied infinite number of different rules. The difference in our perception of the situations is determined by the difference in the rules we apply to them. In order to find a common ground for understanding of a situation we should elaborate common rules of its interpretation. Common rules create for us a common world. In this sense, we can say that my world is the world of my language. At the same, time it is also the world of the other subjects since they use the same rules of interpretation.
In his work On certainty Wittgenstein (2008) describes it the following way. We tend to expect people who are close to us to percept things the same way us we do since they have the same experience while the further a person from us the more different understanding of the world and the facts we expect them to have because they have different experience. If we explain it in terms of Philosophical Investigations, this is due to the fact that we learned to apply rules of the language game together with the people who are close to us. Thus, since we had the same experience in learning how to follow rules we expect people to apply them the same way. We exist - at least partially - in the same world with them.
Key concepts: rule following and private language
However, here another problem emerges. Rules determine our understanding of the world. But what determines our understanding of rules? How can we be sure that it is the same for me and for another person? How can even I be sure that I myself apply the same rule through time? How do I know that I apply this rule and not that if many rules can be applied in this situation? Wittgenstein puts it this way “This was our paradox: no course of action could be determined by a rule, because any course of action can be made out to accord with the rule” (201).
Saul Kripke (1982) develops the investigation of this problem into the Kripkenstein paradox or rule-following paradox that he demonstrates with the help of the example of plus and quus. He says that in the course of our lives we performed a finite number of logical or mathematical operations. Consequently, there are operations we have never performed and we know nothing about their results before we perform them. Let us imagine that there is an X and we have never performed addition on this X. Let us also imagine that there is a quus function, which is absolutely similar to plus function in all cases except one case with this X. Since we have never performed additional operations to X we cannot know if we used plus or quus function before we start performing such operations to X and encounter the one operation that has different result from plus function. In such a way, we do not and cannot know if we are following a particular rule in a particular case. And there is no any superlative fact that could give us a hint on what rule we are following.
The solution suggested by Wittgenstein according to Kripke for the problem of rule-following may seem quite peculiar. According to Saul Kripke, he suggests not thinking about it as long as we do not encounter misunderstanding and correspond to the expectations of other language users. Kripke suggests that this solution is skeptical, as Wittgenstein does not refute skepticism about the correctness of rule following. Gordon Park Baker and Peter Hacker (Бейкер, Хакер 2008), however, criticized him arguing that Wittgenstein never embraced skepticism. Nevertheless, even in his early philosophy Wittgenstein stated “Skepticism is not irrefutable, but obviously nonsensical, when it tries to raise doubts where no question can be asked” (6.51). He did not try to refute skepticism because it seemed pointless to him. There is no basis neither for confirmation of the fact that someone follows a particular rule nor for refutation of it until there is a conflict in the practice of rule following by different subjects. In this case, when facing misunderstanding the subjects will correct each other in accordance with the ways their community uses the language.
This is why for the later Wittgenstein a private language - another important topic according to Kripke's interpretation, which serves as the other side of the coin to the problem of rule following -, a language that will be understandable for only one person is impossible. Otherwise, there will be no one who could confirm that the rules of the language are applied correctly. In this case, we will not be able to be certain even for just a bit if we correctly follow the rules or not because nothing in our appearance, our behavior or our minds can show that we follow this rule and not that. We again find ourselves in the world of uncertainty that belongs only to us. In a sense, private language is a solipsist language Even though Kripke does not directly call Wittgenstein a solipsist in any way, it is not a coincidence that on a par with David Hume he compares him with George Berkeley whose theory would be solipsist if it was carried out strictly and this is what Wittgenstein tries to move away from. Stating that private language is impossible Wittgenstein confirms that the primary function of language is communication and not just mere description because this description should be done for someone to understand it and not just for the sake of description itself.
In the later Wittgenstein's philosophy language still determines how one percepts the world. However, this “one” is not a transcendental subject anymore. This is a subject among other subjects that exist in the world together. They share the world, at least partially, and in such a way create a kind of collective subject, a community that shares and determines the practices of interpretation. If they do not understand each other that means that their usage of language became different at some point, they follow rules differently and because of that live in different worlds.
Language with its rules is a bridge that connects their worlds making it non-solipsist, common. It is not an a priori characteristic of the subject but a human creation subjected to human will that can create and change the rules according to the situation - but not by itself, the language cannot subject to only one person. Universal, purely descriptive language that the early Wittgenstein dreamed of and that could solve all philosophical problems by showing that philosophical propositions are meaningless because they contradict to the logic is now impossible and actually never was possible. Language is not based on logic because “'Talking' (whether out loud or silently) and 'thinking' are not concepts of the same kind; even though they are in closest connection” (Wittgenstein, 1986: 217). Philosophy does not aim to clarify propositions and find out whether their structure does not contain logical contradictions and all words in the propositions have meaning anymore. Rather it aims to understand how it is possible to say anything and be understood at all - that is the main problem of rule-following.
Philosophy should be concerned not so much about the description of world or the subject but about the intersubjective I borrow phenomenological concepts for interpretation of Wittgenstein's ideas here because there are many parallels between him and phenomenologists, which are often pointed out by different researchers (Dwyer, 1989; Hintikka, 1997; Ihde, 1975; Spiegelberg, 1986). For example, in his mid-period work On Certainty (2008) he reproduces Edmund Husserl's argumentation from Cartesian Mediations (Гуссерль, 2010) that he used to refute solipsism and expands it in the domain of language.. The mind of one subject - since nothing in one's behavior or mind can show how one follows and interprets a particular rule - is unavailable for cognition by another subject. The world itself can be interpreted in infinite number of ways and, in a way, it is unavailable for cognition too. Language connects the subject with the world but it is only possible in the intersubjective space. Otherwise, this connection will be absolutely uncertain.
Everything we can tell about the subject and the world comes from how they are represented in the language, which creates intersubjective, public space for their representation. That representation is the only truth available to us. The meaning of this truth is coordinated by the subjects in the process of language usage and explanation of meaning of what they wanted to say and meant by that and that. This process can be also called deliberation.
What makes language suitable for the purpose of representation of the subjects is the fact that it does and does not belong to the subject at the same time. On the one hand, language determines how the subject sees the world. The subject in one's turn is capable of choosing which rules to follow and how to follow them in a particular situation. Language game is flexible and open for interpretation. On the other hand, the subject cannot determine the rules of the language game on one's own. One should always cooperate with other subjects if one wants to follow particular rules because it is the other subjects who witness one's following the rules and decide whether it corresponds to theirs or not. One cannot rely on oneself in that because even our memory can be unreliable and the subject will not notice if it turns out to deceiving.
Conclusion
In such a way, in his early philosophy Wittgenstein sets the subject as the limit of the world and denies the possibility to talk about the reality beyond what can be said. He describes a transcendental and in a way solipsist subject, which is that dominated European post-Cartesian philosophy. In his later views, according to Saul Kripke he deconstructs this system dissolving the subject in language that creates intersubjective space. In this later system, the existence of individual [rational] subject, which uses a private language understandable only for oneself, is impossible because no rules are possible under control of only one subject because since in this case nothing and no one that can point out to the violation of the rules there is no control at all. The subject always exists together with other subjects in the intersubjective world created by language that they use together. If the early Wittgenstein tried to blur the line between the subject and the world, the later Wittgenstein blurs the line between the subjects themselves as they and their worlds are interpenetrating and their worlds are mingling even though in their public representation as the ones who speak and the ones who hear or respond they are definitely different.
Chapter II. Political implications of Wittgenstein's theory
Introduction
A close analysis of the discussion of Wittgensteinian philosophy is important because different interpretations of his ideas can lead to different implication in politics. Wittgenstein's ideas, especially the idea of rule-following, were used by many political theorists in order to defend particular social policies and the choice of the policy depended on their interpretation of his works. This chapter is mainly devoted to a brief but broad overview of the discussion surrounding Wittgenstein's ideas in the political philosophy.
Revolutionary roots of the early Wittgenstein's ideas and conservative readings of the later Wittgenstein
Wittgenstein himself, Bertrand Russel, Rudolf Carnap and other positivists and members of the Vienna Circle were mostly socialists. Wittgenstein did not engage in political philosophy but nevertheless expressed sympathy for the socialists and traveled to the Soviet Union. Russell (2004) has an essay titled “The Case for Socialism”. Martin Puchner (2005) notes that The Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus in essence and form was a manifesto similar to The Manifesto of the Communist Party. Besides, the Tractatus became a foundation for a collective Manifesto written in 1929 where the members of the Vienna Circle call for solidarity “to all friends of scientific worldview” against “the reactionary forces of metaphysics and theological thinking”. Their attempt was similar to the intentions of scientific socialists to overcome all social problems with the help of science.
This manifesto of the "scientistic world view" has fully absorbed the language of the socialist and the avant-garde manifesto, including its revolutionary rhetoric, its high concentration of exclamation marks, and its use of bold letters and caps that underline central slogans and demands (ibid, 286)
Carnap corresponded with Karl Popper regarding Popper's book The Open Society and its Enemies, where he criticizes Marx and scientific socialism (Notturno 1999). This criticism reflects his ideas about the incompleteness of all knowledge that was opposed to the modernist intentions of Carnap and Wittgenstein to overcome all the problems of philosophy with the help of a logical analysis of the language (Carnap 1932).
Friedrich von Hayek (1982), who helped Popper publish The Open Society, takes a very similar position to the one that was expressed by Popper but he used arguments that are also very similar to the ideas expressed by the latter Wittgenstein who partially renounced his early views. Hayek put forward an epistemological argument against socialist economic planning that was later developed by Antony Giddens (1994). It should be noted, that Hayek comes to his ideas independently of Wittgenstein and derives his ideas predominantly from Kant and Hume (Pleasants 1997) but Giddens developed this argument on the basis of the latter Wittgensteinian philosophy and rule-following paradox. According to this argument, economic planning is impossible because the knowledge of any person or a group of people who could organize such planning is limited. If the planning board alone are to assign values these values will be devoid of any standard of truth. Whatever is going to seem right to the board will be proclaimed right. Consequently, on Kripke's interpretation of Wittgenstein's private-language argument, there could be no objective correctness at all here. According to Hayek and Giddens the knowledge that is necessary for successful coordination of the economy is distributed among the population and rooted in its ability to follow the rules. In this case, he relies on the theory of tacit knowledge of Michael Polanyi (1967). This knowledge is possessed only by the entire population as a whole, but not by separate individuals.
Nigel Pleasants (1997) thinks that Hayek' and Giddens' arguments are deeply conservative even though they pose their views as liberalism. They use Wittgenstein to prove that a particular social structure - the one that already exists, the status quo - is epistemologically superior and for this reason it should not be changed. However, there are more traditional conservative readings of Wittgenstein's theory that rely on the same logic. For example, John Gray (1984) tries to show using again Hayek's ideas that “forms of life” as basic constitutive traditions of social life are simply given to us, and must be accepted by us. Kristуf Nyнri (1982) famous for his attempts to link Wittgenstein with conservatism also tries to undermine his critical potential trying to depict “forms of life” as the ultimate givenness. Conservative thinkers try to connect Wittgenstein's thinking with the political philosophy of Michael Oakeshott (1991) who thought that political governance must be grounded in “practical knowledge” and that conservatism is a “disposition to prefer the familiar to the unknown”. The same way, in their opinion, Wittgenstein tends to describe language as an everyday practice and explain its functioning saying “this is simply what I do” (PI, §217).
Criticism of these approaches
Karl Popper was sometimes called in Cambridge “the official opposition”. He extensively criticized the revolutionary scientism of the Vienna Circle together with Marxist ideas. In The Open Society (2012) does not completely abandon the attempts of scientific rearrangement of the world. He even supports Marx's ethical arguments against capitalism. He only criticizes the path proposed by Marx saying that his historicism leads to mysticism - which is also often ascribed to Wittgenstein (i.e. McGuinness 1966) - and, as a result, to fascism that is based on it (Notturno 1999, 40-42).
Popper did not say that socialism cannot be scientific. He said that no science can be `scientific' in the way Marx thought. Science, on Popper's account, is not a set of a priori certain or even empirically justified true beliefs. It is an everfallible, never-justified, and frequently changing process of conjecture and refutation--a process of proposing hypotheses to solve our problems, testing them against experience, and readjusting the one in light of the other in an effort to make the two of them fit. (Ibid, 48-49)
At the same time, he believes that freedom that liberals value so much cannot be maintained without when there is high inequality. However, inequality cannot be overcome without the preservation of freedom and democracy. It is no accident that, as he believes, Plato, whom he criticizes on a par with Hegel and Marx, comes to the conclusion that the most just social order can be built only by the philosopher king but this philosopher king in his methods is indistinguishable for an outside observer from a tyrant .
Criticizing Hayek and Giddens Nigel Pleasants (1997) notes that in their view of knowledge are more likely to be the skeptics Wittgenstein argues with. They confuse the different meanings of “possession of knowledge” implying by it direct accessibility of experience for individuals. This experience since it is directly accessed cannot be doubted while Wittgenstein's knowledge is dialectically connected with doubt, the ability to describe it to another, and the possibility to be either confirmed or refuted. Wittgenstein's view presupposes that if agents act differently they should at some point face their disagreement and resolve it rationally trough deliberation. Their habits can no way represent the ultimate truth that cannot be contested. In order for their practices to be considered as rules they need to be known and understandable for other agents so they could judge if the rules are followed in a right or wrong way. Without mutual exchange of the information and the process of mutual correction and rationalization, their habits cannot be even counted as rules because they are random.
Similarly, different meanings of “ownership” are confused by free-market proponents criticized by Marx and Engels (1964) when they say that even after the abolition of private property individuals will still own themselves and their private experience. However, both knowledge and property are rooted in social institutions and structures that certify them to other people; they cannot depend on individuals. Private experience is not a matter of public identification and hence not a property. For this reason both private language and “private owning” so to say - in a sense that it is confirmed by only one individual - are impossible: they do not give the possibility of their public identification.
Thus, Giddens and Hayek not only describe an epistemic state of affairs but privilege a certain type of knowledge, namely the most distributed tacit knowledge based on the spontaneous desires and preferences of individuals, which supposedly should be formed in a spontaneous order. However, as Daniel Luban (2019) notes, speaking of a spontaneous order Hayek arbitrarily determines who are the external actors for the economic system and who are the internal ones. A large company can arise in the same way due to self-interested behavior and begin to impose its own rules as a bureaucratic machine, which incidentally also arose as a result of such behavior, competition of self-interested individuals, and spontaneous order. Proponents of the spontaneous order theory say that all plans and reforms have unintended consequences because people will always behave in unimaginable ways, therefore the results of the reforms cannot be predicted. However, they simultaneously state that the results of spontaneous order are predictable. For example, the predictable market arises from spontaneous economic activity. Therefore, Polanyi's argument can be directed back against Giddens and Hayek: it is not that individuals reveal their knowledge through the price mechanism; rather, the price mechanism records responses of individuals, which are largely the product of their social environment. Consequently, since the spontaneous order is organized by the entrepreneurs tacit knowledge it thereby becomes impossible to question their competence or rationality and whatever is going to seem right to the entrepreneur will be right.
Bernard Williams (2019) points out that communitarian political thinkers who oppose liberals relying in the idea of the ration of an individual to the community rather that to the human rights and freedoms use the same logic interpreting Wittgenstein as the conservatives. They reject liberal attempts to find objective political values on the grounds of rational reasoning, pluralism and procedural fairness regarding such values as excessively abstract and questioning commitment to pluralism as the most just social arrangement and a sufficiently binding social force. Just like Kripke, they regard any social arrangements as the result of inherently particular historical and environmental conditions. Instead of universal pluralist values, they promote particularistic approach giving their preference to more or less culturally homogeneous societies formed around shared values.
Although Williams shares communitarian concerns regarding ahistorical and out contextual universalism of liberals he rejects the conclusions made by communitarians. He thinks that they overestimate the differences between different communities. If values and meanings were indeed as context and society dependent as communitarians think the differences between societies would be incomprehensible. In that case, it would be Impossible for modern people to understand Homeric heroes, for example, and any ancient or foreign literature would be of no use for us at all. Nevertheless, we find ourselves capable to relate to these characters and learn some lessons from them.
The case is plurality is a precondition of modern social life. Any society, however homogenous it is has to face alternatives to their ways of life both inside and outside overlapping with other societies and in such a way creating a new dimension of homogeneity and heterogeneity. That is why Williams finds both universality of reason - be it liberal or socialist universality - and particularity of communitarianism inadequate to describe the complicated reality.
Wittgenstein and the critique of liberalism and socialism
The remark about liberal and socialist universalism is important here. Liberalism and socialism can be considered as two modernist “grand projects” or grand narratives as Jean-Franзois Lyotard (2010) would call them. They are both aimed to solve all political problems and disagreements by the means of reason and science - a project that Lyotard is very skeptical of and that he criticizes again using the latter Wittgenstein. As Hekma, Oosterhuis & Steakley (1995) point out they inherit the Enlightenment's distinction between sin and crime, passion and reason, private and public, family and the state but treat differently the contradictions that emerge from the fact that this distinction is an illusion and private is actually political and therefore part of the public. This distinction was essential to liberalism so liberals had to adopt double standards condoning promiscuous behavior of bourgeoisie men with lower class women because their (men's) private life was sacred but at the same time since sexually transmitted diseases were a subject of the public matter controlling sex-life of these women.
Marx and Engels (Marx 1964; Marx and Engels 1968; Engels 1968) criticized the existence of these double standards but never questioned the distinction itself. Instead, they argued that the fall of capitalism would reinforce the family bounding men the same way it bounds women arguing with social utopists such as Charles Fourier, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon or Henri Saint-Simon who on the contrary envisioned dissolution of the family and the community of women. As a result, communist governments ended up considering family a public matter and trying to control private life of individuals the same way liberal governments controlled such its manifestations as prostitution and homosexuality.
Liberal and socialist approach to this distinction is illuminating. As it was said earlier, proponents of scientific socialism wanted to use science and reason not only to solve all philosophical problems but wanted to solve all political problems and resolve all disagreements. Liberal thinkers like John Rawls (1971), Isaiah Berlin (1969) or Jьrgen Habermas (1984; 1989) want, on the contrary, to retain the sphere where disagreement and deflection are possible. Just as dispositionalists want to find objective criterions for normal subjects and circumstances that would ensure that the dispositions of the subjects' interpretation of the rules provoked by interactions with objects to be correct, liberals want to find objective criterions for delineation of such a sphere, where the rules of nature would be fallible and disagreement would be possible.
However, in this goal they actually subvert the meaning of the Political. The very fact of final and rational delineation destroys it. As Chantal Mouffe (2000) points out both Rawls and Habermas try to avoid competition, agonism and disagreement that is in the basis of democracy and politics. Instead, they both reserve the space for pluralism outside political process: Rawls positions it in the private sphere that is opposed to the public sphere; Habermas does that with the ethical sphere that is opposed to morals. In order for their political projects to be functional, all individuals should be connected by rational consensus that excludes the possibility of competition and agonism. In these systems, politics should be protected against the consequences of pluralism. Not denying the necessity to restrict political pluralism in order to protect democracy from non-democratic forms of politics that drives Rawls's and Habermas's desire to restrict disagreement to the spheres of private or ethical because they confuse agonism with antagonism Mouffe suggests that we should just acknowledge the political nature of such exclusion and not try to preset it as objective and rational criterion especially since politics in her opinion is driven not by reason but by passion. Mouffe, referencing Oakeshott and his interpretation of Wittgenstein, notices that rationality is not enough for establishment of political order and political community. Any political order should be grounded in practices corresponding to this order because it is not enough just to agree with it but it is essential that the citizens constantly confirm their devotion and obligations to this order before each other. This order cannot be purely theoretical; it should be a form of life.
Beyond this criticism towards a positive political theory based on Wittgenstein
Mouffe's own project of agonistic democracy is skeptical of a possibility of any compromise between different political groups and agents. She thinks that politics are based on definition and constant redefinition of the borders of the political community - it is in essence a question of inclusion and exclusion. Instead, she suggest accepting the fact that any political consensus is based on hegemony and therefore it is legitimate since it's proponents managed to impose it on others. This interpretation is again deeply conservative and communitarian in Kripkean sense according to which anything that anything that is proclaimed right by the hegemon is performatively made right.
An alternative to this view can be found in political theory of Philip Pettit who emphasizes the ideal of freedom as non-domination that can be opposed to Mouffe's hegemony as it represents domination. Pettit also bases his ideas on Wittgenstein but he begins by suggesting his own solution to the problem of rule-following and then extending it on political philosophy.
Although Pettit is a prominent political thinker there has been little research on his epistemological groundings of political ontology that is based on Wittgenstein. Soham Shiva (2016) is the only one whom I have found who tries to connect Pettit's research on Wittgenstein with political philosophy. However, he uses Wittgenstein to criticize Habermas in a similar way equating Mouffe does. He equates Habermas political ontology with Pettit's epistemology through the idea of second-order beliefs and desires that will be considered in the next chapter. In his opinion, Habermas's account of communicative rationality is too theoretical and lacks practical approach that is envisioned by Wittgenstein's concept of language as “a form of life”.
He connects Pettit with Habermas because he thinks that second-order beliefs represent Habermas's normative theoretical approach. For some reason, Shiva does not consider Pettit's own political philosophy that in no way can be reduced to Habermas's ideas or the idea of higher-order beliefs, desires and volitions. He misses the fact that in Pettit's theory the existence of second-order beliefs entails the existence of higher-order beliefs, which leads to vicious infinite regression of higher and higher-order beliefs. This infinite regression is not satisfying for Pettit so he suggests an alternative in the theory of freedom as discursive control that requires from the agents to be involved in discursive practices together with others and actively endorse their beliefs and desires. This approach is based on his solution to the rule-following paradox that I am going to analyze in the next chapter.
Conclusion
To sum it up, early Wittgenstein and his Cambridge colleagues tried to create a philosophy that would change the world eliminating all its flaws with the help of reason and science. This approach proved unattainable because any knowledge is limited and there cannot be any final solution or absolute knowledge. Consequently, there cannot be a political solution that would satisfy everyone and get rid of any disagreement.
Wittgenstein had to partially renounce the universalism of his early views and move to a philosophy that concentrates on local language arrangements, language games that work only in particular situations and particular communities of language users in order to account for all the difference of the real linguistic practices. This move was often interpreted by the conservatives not only for the criticism of any universalism but also for the support of the status quo as epistemologically superior.
However, some critics such as Bernard Williams and Chantal Mouffe note that this view requires universalism no less than Wittgenstein's early philosophy at least at the level of the community that holds on to its practices. They point out that pluralism is a precondition of any political life and any philosophy and Wittgenstein knew it. On this premise Williams criticizes both the early Wittgenstein views and the conservative interpretations of his later philosophy but he does not propose any positive philosophy. Mouffe suggests that pluralism means eternal struggle for hegemony between communities, which is only an extension of conservative interpretations.
Philip Pettit offers a model of politics and ontology based on his own development of Wittgenstein's ideas that presupposes disagreement, fallibility and constant reconsideration due to new information and possible disagreements between the agents. Unlike conservatives and communitarians who are prone to stick to the already existing course of things because they thing that language and politics as a form of life are a given he remains devoted to rationality and change. The main driver of this change is pluralism that inevitably leads to discrepancies in responses and the main solution to the problem of pluralism is rational negotiation that determines, which conditions the responses of the agents are favorable and which are not. In the next chapter, I am going to get back to the rule-following paradox in order to show how Pettit solves it and how his solution is implemented in his political philosophy.
...Подобные документы
Language picture of the world, factors of formation. The configuration of the ideas embodied in the meaning of the words of the native language. Key ideas for Russian language picture of the world are. Presentation of the unpredictability of the world.
реферат [17,2 K], добавлен 11.10.2015Why study Indian philosophy. Why study philosophy. The method of asking questions. The Katha Upanishad. The method of analogy. Outline of Indian Philosophy. The Four Vedas. Monism versus Non-dualism. The Epic Period. Sutra Period. The Modern Period.
презентация [661,8 K], добавлен 26.02.2015Confucianism as the source of the fundamental outlook for the Chinese. The history of its occurrence during the reign of the Han dynasty. Significant differences of this philosophy from other major canons. Idealistic views on the development of society.
презентация [889,1 K], добавлен 13.11.2014Fr. Nietzsche as German thinker who lived in the second half of the Nineteenth Century. The essence of the concept of "nihilism". Peculiarities of the philosophy of Socrates. Familiarity with Nietzsche. Analysis of drama "Conscience as Fatality".
доклад [15,3 K], добавлен 09.03.2013What is meant by Kant’s "Copernican Revolution"? What is the "Transcendental Aesthetic" about? Explain what Kant means by intuition, pure intuition, empirical intuition; concept, pure concept, empirical concept; transcendent.
курсовая работа [23,0 K], добавлен 09.04.2007In a certain sense there is a place in Buddhism for Absolute Self and that we have to forget this idea like all other ideas if we are to succeed in final meditation, which brings us to the Reality beyond all concepts.
курсовая работа [18,5 K], добавлен 09.04.2007The Abelards solution of the problem of universals is neither a realistic no a nominalistic one, or, in other words, it is in the same degree nominalistic as it is realistic.
курсовая работа [23,3 K], добавлен 09.04.2007Governmental theory - one of important and perspective directions of modern political ideas. Political sphere from complete. The political phenomena are in structures, prevailing over paradigms in connection with the complex of the public phenomena.
реферат [24,3 K], добавлен 22.11.2010The term "political system". The theory of social system. Classification of social system. Organizational and institutional subsystem. Sociology of political systems. The creators of the theory of political systems. Cultural and ideological subsystem.
реферат [18,8 K], добавлен 29.04.2016Analysis of Rousseau's social contract theory and examples of its connection with the real world. Structure of society. Principles of having an efficient governmental system. Theory of separation of powers. The importance of censorship and religion.
статья [13,1 K], добавлен 30.11.2014The study of political discourse. Political discourse: representation and transformation. Syntax, translation, and truth. Modern rhetorical studies. Aspects of a communication science, historical building, the social theory and political science.
лекция [35,9 K], добавлен 18.05.2011Political power as one of the most important of its kind. The main types of political power. The functional analysis in the context of the theory of social action community. Means of political activity related to the significant material cost-us.
реферат [11,8 K], добавлен 10.05.2011A cosmological model to explain the origins of matter, energy, space, time the Big Bang theory asserts that the universe began at a certain point in the distant past. Pre-twentieth century ideas of Universe’s origins. Confirmation of the Big Bang theory.
реферат [37,2 K], добавлен 25.06.2010The Rule of Law is what some philosophers have called an essentially contestable concept. Grounds of agreement and disagreement. Four ideal-typical conceptions of the Rule of Law. Toward an integrated theory. An ideal that can never be realized perfectly.
доклад [30,1 K], добавлен 16.06.2013Theory of economics was created and is developed by the economists of different schools. Main article: History of Economics. Areas of study. Techniques. Language and reasoning. Development of economic thought. The system of economic relations.
реферат [22,6 K], добавлен 12.05.2008Definition of Leadership. Trait theory. How this theory works. Origin and Analysis and basics Pre-conditions for effective use of Trait theory. Inborn leadership characteristics. Process of impact and interaction among the leader and his followers.
реферат [436,9 K], добавлен 24.09.2014Public choice is an application of neoclassical economic tools. James Buchanan the developer of the Theory of the Public choice. The most important contribution of Public Choice Theory is that it recognizes that politicians are motivated by self interest.
презентация [273,0 K], добавлен 03.04.2012A discussion of the political problems of proletarian revolution some clarification on a number of points in Marx’s social theory. The proletariat is the working class peculiar to capitalist relayions of production in Marx’s theory. Working-class circles.
реферат [39,1 K], добавлен 23.06.2010The central elements of the original Community method. A new "intergovernmentalist" school of integration theory emerged, liberal intergovernmentalism. Constructivism, and reshaping European identities and preferences and integration theory today.
практическая работа [29,4 K], добавлен 20.03.2010History of interpreting and establishing of the theory. Translation and interpreting. Sign-language communication between speakers. Modern Western Schools of translation theory. Models and types of interpreting. Simultaneous and machine translation.
курсовая работа [45,2 K], добавлен 26.01.2011